Loading...

Messages

Proposals

Stuck in your homework and missing deadline? Get urgent help in $10/Page with 24 hours deadline

Get Urgent Writing Help In Your Essays, Assignments, Homeworks, Dissertation, Thesis Or Coursework & Achieve A+ Grades.

Privacy Guaranteed - 100% Plagiarism Free Writing - Free Turnitin Report - Professional And Experienced Writers - 24/7 Online Support

Business ethics 9th edition pdf free

08/10/2021 Client: muhammad11 Deadline: 2 Day

Feeding The World

3 PARAGRAPHS
As Hite and Seitz (2016) show in Chapter 3: Food, there is enough food produced and available to feed the entire world every day. However, for various reasons, millions still go hungry, making food security—having consistent access to adequate nutritional food—a persistent global social problem in both developing and developed countries.

Where do most of the world’s hungry live?

What are two causes of hunger and two problems that result?

What are some potential consequences and benefits to using biotechnologies in developing countries? Based on the research currently available, should developing countries pursue the use of biotechnologies? Why or why not?

Be sure to inform your response with facts from sources. Use our ebook/textbook each week and at least one scholarly outside source. You must cite sources in-text and give a full citation at the end of your response.

Australia • Brazil • Mexico • Singapore • United Kingdom • United States

William H. Shaw San Jose State University

Bus iness eth ics

9t h e di t ion

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 1 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

82088_index_ptg01_465-486.indd 481 9/3/15 9:08 AM

This is an electronic version of the print textbook. Due to electronic rights restrictions, some third party content may be suppressed. Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. The publisher reserves the right to remove content from this title at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it. For valuable information on pricing, previous editions, changes to current editions, and alternate formats, please visit www.cengage.com/highered to search by ISBN#, author, title, or keyword for materials in your areas of interest.

Important Notice: Media content referenced within the product description or the product text may not be available in the eBook version.

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

© 2017, 2014, 2011, Cengage Learning

ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. No part of this work covered by the copyright herein may be reproduced, transmitted, stored, or used in any form or by any means graphic, electronic, or mechanical, including but not limited to photocopying, recording, scanning, digitizing, taping, web distribution, information networks, or information storage and retrieval systems, except as permitted under Section 107 or 108 of the 1976 United States Copyright Act, without the prior written permission of the publisher.

Library of Congress Control Number: 2015948749

Student Edition:

ISBN: 978-1-305-58208-8

Loose-leaf Edition:

ISBN: 978-1-305-87538-8

Cengage Learning 20 Channel Center Street Boston, MA 02210 USA

Cengage Learning is a leading provider of customized learning solutions with employees residing in nearly 40 different countries and sales in more than 125 countries around the world. Find your local representative at www.cengage.com.

Cengage Learning products are represented in Canada by Nelson Education, Ltd.

To learn more about Cengage Learning Solutions, visit www.cengage.com.

Purchase any of our products at your local college store or at our preferred online store www.cengagebrain.com.

Business Ethics, Ninth Edition William H. Shaw

Product Director: Paul Banks

Product Manager: Debra Matteson

Content Developer: Jessica Wang-Strykowski

Product Assistant: Michelle Forbes

Marketing Manager: Sean Ketchem

IP Analyst: Alexandra Ricciardi

IP Project Manager: Betsy Hathaway

Manufacturing Planner: Sandee Milewski

Art and Design Direction, Production Management, and Composition: Lumina Datamatics, Inc.

Cover and Interior Image: Fuse/Getty Images

Printed in the United States of America Print Number: 01 Print Year: 2015

For product information and technology assistance, contact us at Cengage Learning Customer & Sales Support, 1-800-354-9706

For permission to use material from this text or product, submit all requests online at www.cengage.com/permissions.

Further permissions questions can be emailed to permissionrequest@cengage.com.

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 2 9/4/15 5:46 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

WCN: 02-200-203

iii

PREFACE viii

Pa rt On e | MOr a l Ph i lOsOPh y a n d Busi n e s s 1

ch a pte r 1 the n ature of Mor al it y 1 Ethics 3 Moral versus Nonmoral Standards 5 Religion and Morality 11 Ethical Relativism 13 Having Moral Principles 15 Morality and Personal Values 19 Individual Integrity and Responsibility 20 Moral Reasoning 24 Study Corner 31 Case 1.1: Made in the U.S.A.—Dumped in Brazil, Africa, Iraq . . . 32 Case 1.2: Loose Money 35 Case 1.3: Just Drop off the Key, Lee 36 Case 1.4: The A7D Affair 39

ch a pte r 2 norMat iv e theor ies of e th ics 4 3 Consequentialist and Nonconsequentialist Theories 45 Egoism 46 Utilitarianism 49 Kant’s Ethics 56 Other Nonconsequentialist Perspectives 62 Utilitarianism Once More 68 Moral Decision Making: A Practical Approach 70 Study Corner 73 Case 2.1: Hacking into Harvard 74 Case 2.2: The Ford Pinto 77 Case 2.3: Blood for Sale 80

contents

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 3 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

iv Contents

cha pter 3 Just ice and econoMic d istr iBut ion 83 The Nature of Justice 86 The Utilitarian View 89 The Libertarian Approach 93 Rawls’s Theory of Justice 100 Study Corner 109 Case 3.1: Eminent Domain 110 Case 3.2: Battling over Bottled Water 112 Case 3.3: Poverty in America 114

Pa rt t wO | a M e r ic a n Busi n e s s a n d its Ba sis 117

cha pter 4 the n ature of ca p ital isM 117 Capitalism 119 Key Features of Capitalism 122 Two Arguments for Capitalism 124 Criticisms of Capitalism 128 Today’s Economic Challenges 136 Study Corner 142 Case 4.1: Catastrophe in Bangladesh 143 Case 4.2: Licensing and Laissez Faire 145 Case 4.3: One Nation under Walmart 148 Case 4.4: A New Work Ethic? 151 Case 4.5: Casino Gambling on Wall Street 152 Case 4.6: Paying College Athletes 154

cha pter 5 corpor at ions 156 The Limited-Liability Company 158 Corporate Moral Agency 160 Rival Views of Corporate Responsibility 164 Debating Corporate Responsibility 171 Institutionalizing Ethics within Corporations 176 Study Corner 183 Case 5.1: Yahoo in China 184 Case 5.2: Drug Dilemmas 186 Case 5.3: Free Speech or False Advertising? 189 Case 5.4: Corporations and Religious Faith 191 Case 5.5: Charity to Scouts? 193 Case 5.6: Corporate Taxation 195

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 4 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

Contents v

Pa rt t h r e e | Busi n e s s a n d sOci et y 197

ch a pte r 6 consuMers 197 Product Safety 199 Other Areas of Business Responsibility 211 Deception and Unfairness in Advertising 220 The Debate over Advertising 230 Study Corner 234 Case 6.1: Breast Implants 235 Case 6.2: Hot Coffee at McDonald’s 237 Case 6.3: Sniffing Glue Could Snuff Profits 239 Case 6.4: Closing the Deal 240 Case 6.5: The Rise and Fall of Four Loko 243

ch a pte r 7 the en v ironMent 24 5 Business and Ecology 249 The Ethics of Environmental Protection 252 Achieving Our Environmental Goals 258 Delving Deeper into Environmental Ethics 263 Study Corner 271 Case 7.1: Hazardous Homes in Herculaneum 272 Case 7.2: Poverty and Pollution 275 Case 7.3: The Fordasaurus 277 Case 7.4: The Fight over the Redwoods 279 Case 7.5: Palm Oil and Its Problems 282

Pa rt fOu r | t h e OrG a n i Z at iOn a n d t h e PeOPl e i n it 284

ch a pte r 8 the Work pl ace (1) : Bas ic issues 28 4 Civil Liberties in the Workplace 285 Hiring 291 Promotions 297 Discipline and Discharge 299 Wages 303 Labor Unions 307 Study Corner 316 Case 8.1: AIDS in the Workplace 317 Case 8.2: Web Porn at Work 319

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 5 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

vi Contents

Case 8.3: Speaking Out about Malt 320 Case 8.4: Have Gun, Will Travel . . . to Work 321 Case 8.5: Union Discrimination 324

cha pter 9 the Work pl ace ( 2 ) : today’s challenges 326 Organizational Influence in Private Lives 327 Testing and Monitoring 332 Working Conditions 338 Redesigning Work 347 Study Corner 351 Case 9.1: Unprofessional Conduct? 352 Case 9.2: Testing for Honesty 353 Case 9.3: She Snoops to Conquer 356 Case 9.4: Protecting the Unborn at Work 357 Case 9.5: Swedish Daddies 360

cha pter 10 Mor al choices fac ing eMpl oy ees 363 Obligations to the Firm 364 Abuse of Official Position 368 Bribes and Kickbacks 374 Gifts and Entertainment 378 Conflicting Obligations 380 Whistle-Blowing 383 Self-Interest and Moral Obligation 387 Study Corner 391 Case 10.1: Changing Jobs and Changing Loyalties 392 Case 10.2: Conflicting Perspectives on Conflicts of Interest 393 Case 10.3: Inside Traders or Astute Observers? 395 Case 10.4: The Housing Allowance 397 Case 10.5: Ethically Dubious Conduct 398

cha pter 11 JoB d iscr iMinat ion 4 01 The Meaning of Job Discrimination 403 Evidence of Discrimination 405 Affirmative Action: The Legal Context 410 Affirmative Action: The Moral Issues 415 Comparable Worth 418 Sexual Harassment 420

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 6 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

Contents vii

Study Corner 424 Case 11.1: Minority Set-Asides 425 Case 11.2: Hoop Dreams 427 Case 11.3: Raising the Ante 429 Case 11.4: Consenting to Sexual Harassment 430 Case 11.5: Facial Discrimination 433

SUGGESTIONS FOR FURTHER READING 435

NOTES 439

INDEX 465

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 7 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

viii

preface It is difficult to imagine an area of study that has greater importance to society or greater relevance to students than business ethics. As this text enters its ninth edition, business ethics has become a well- established academic subject. Most colleges and universities offer courses in it, and scholarly interest continues to grow.

Yet some people still scoff at the idea of business ethics, jesting that the very concept is an oxymoron. To be sure, recent years have seen the newspapers filled with lurid stories of corporate misconduct and felo- nious behavior by individual businesspeople, and many suspect that what the media report represents only the proverbial tip of the iceberg. However, these scandals should prompt a reflective person not to make fun of business ethics but rather to think more deeply about the nature and purpose of business in our society and about the ethical choices individuals must inevitably make in their business and professional lives.

Business ethics has an interdisciplinary character. Questions of economic policy and business practice intertwine with issues in politics, sociology, and organizational theory. Although business ethics remains anchored in philosophy, even here abstract questions in normative ethics and political philosophy mingle with analysis of practical problems and concrete moral dilemmas. Furthermore, business ethics is not just an academic study but also an invitation to reflect on our own values and on our own responses to the hard moral choices that the world of business can pose.

• • •

goal s, org ani Z at ion, and topics Business Ethics has four goals: to expose students to the important moral issues that arise in various business contexts; to provide students with an understanding of the moral, social, and economic environ- ments within which those problems occur; to introduce students to the ethical and other concepts that are relevant for resolving those problems; and to assist students in developing the necessary reasoning and analytical skills for doing so. Although the book’s primary emphasis is on business, its scope extends to related moral issues in other organizational and professional contexts.

The book has four parts. Part One, “Moral Philosophy and Business,” discusses the nature of morality and presents the main theories of normative ethics and the leading approaches to questions of economic justice. Part Two, “American Business and Its Basis,” examines the institutional foundations of business, focusing on capitalism as an economic system and the nature and role of corporations in our society. Part Three, “Business and Society,” concerns moral problems involving business, consumers, and the natural environment. Part Four, “The Organization and the People in It,” identifies a variety of ethical issues and moral challenges that arise out of the interplay of employers and employees within an organization, includ- ing the problem of discrimination.

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 8 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

prefaCe ix

Case studies enhance the main text. These cases vary in kind and in length, but they are all designed to enable instructors and students to pursue further some of the issues discussed in the text and to analyze them in more specific contexts. The case studies should provide a lively springboard for classroom discus- sions and the application of ethical concepts.

Business Ethics covers a wide range of topics relevant to today’s world. Three of these are worth drawing particular attention to.

Business and Globalization

The moral challenges facing business in today’s globalized world economy are well represented in the book and seamlessly integrated into the chapters. For example, Chapter 1 discusses ethical relativism, Chapter 4 outsourcing and globalization, and Chapter 8 overseas bribery and the Foreign Corrupt Practices Act; and there are international examples or comparisons throughout the book. Moreover, almost all the basic issues discussed in the book (such as corporate responsibility, the nature of moral reasoning, and the value of the natural world—to name just three) are as crucial to making moral decisions in an international business context as they are to making them at home. In addition, cases 1.1, 2.3, 4.1, 5.1, 5.2, 6.3, 7.2, 7.5, 9.5, and 10.4 deal explicitly with moral issues arising in today’s global economic system.

The Environment

Because of its ongoing relevance and heightened importance in today’s world, an entire chapter, Chapter 7, with five case studies is devoted to this topic. In particular, the chapter highlights recent environmental disasters, the environmental dilemmas and challenges we face, and their social and business costs, as well as the changing attitude of business toward the environment and ecology.

Health and Health Care

Far from being a narrow academic pursuit, the study of business ethics is relevant to a wide range of important social issues—for example, to health and health care, which is currently the subject of much discussion and debate in the United States. Aspects of this topic are addressed in the text and developed in the following cases: 2.3: Blood for Sale, 4.2: Licensing and Laissez Faire, 5.2: Drug Dilemmas, 6.1: Breast Implants, 8.1: AIDS in the Workplace, and 9.4: Protecting the Unborn at Work.

• • •

changes in th is ed it ion YOUR TEXTBOOK

Instructors who have used the previous edition will find the organization, general content, and overall design of the book familiar. However, the text has been revised throughout, as examples and information have been updated, and the clarity of its discussions and the accuracy of its treatment of both philosophical and empirical issues have been improved. At all times the goal has been to provide a textbook that students will find clear, understandable, and engaging.

Fifty-two case studies—more than ever before—now supplement the main text. Five of them are brand new; a number of the others have been revised or updated. Of the cases that are new to this edi- tion, Case 1.2, “Loose Money,” deals with whether to return cash that has been dropped to its owner;

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 9 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

x prefaCe

Case 4.1, “Catastrophe in Bangladesh,” concerns responsibility for a factory collapse that killed over a thou- sand workers making clothing for Western firms; Case 4.6, “Paying College Athletes,” examines the move to give athletes a greater share of the revenues from college sports; Case 5.4, “Corporations and Religious Faith,” deals with the claim that corporations have a right to do business in a way that reflects the religious beliefs of their owners; and Case 5.6, “Corporate Taxation,” discusses tax avoidance by large corporations.

MindTap

MindTap® Ethics for Shaw’s Business Ethics is a digital learning solution that helps instructors engage and transform today’s students into critical thinkers. Through paths of dynamic assignments and applica- tions that can personalized by instructors (including ethics simulations, quizzing and BBC videos), real-time course analytics and an accessible reader, MindTap helps turn cookie cutter into cutting edge, apathy into engagement, and memorizers into higher-level thinkers.

• • •

Ways of us ing the Book A course in business ethics can be taught in a variety of ways. Instructors have different approaches to the subject, different intellectual and pedagogical goals, and different classroom styles. They emphasize different themes and start at different places. Some of them may prefer to treat the foundational questions of ethical theory thoroughly before moving on to particular moral problems; others reverse this priority. Still other instructors frame their courses around the question of economic justice, the analysis of capitalism, or the debate over corporate social responsibility. Some instructors stress individual moral decision making, others social and economic policy.

Business Ethics permits teachers great flexibility in how they organize their courses. A wide range of theoretical and applied issues are discussed; and the individual chapters, the major sections within them, and the case studies are to a surprising extent self-contained. Instructors can thus teach the book in what- ever order they choose, and they can easily skip or touch lightly on some topics in order to concentrate on others without loss of coherence.

• • •

acknoWledgMents I wish to acknowledge my great debt to the many people whose ideas and writing have influenced me over the years. Philosophy is widely recognized to involve a process of ongoing dialogue. This is nowhere more evident than in the writing to textbooks, whose authors can rarely claim that the ideas being synthesized, organized, and presented are theirs alone. Without my colleagues, without my students, and without a larger philosophical community concerned with business and ethics, this book would not have been possible.

I particularly want to acknowledge my debt to Vincent Barry. Readers familiar with our textbook and reader Moral Issues in Business1 will realize the extent to which I have drawn on material from that work. Business Ethics is, in effect, a revised and updated version of the textbook portion of that collaborative work, and I am very grateful to Vince for permitting me to use our joint work here.

1William H. Shaw and Vincent Barry, Moral Issues in Business, 13th ed. (Boston, Mass.: Cengage Learning, 2016).

82088_FM_ptg01_i-x.indd 10 9/4/15 11:02 AM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

IntroductIon

1

end. Even with the company’s financial demise fast approach- ing, Kenneth Lay was still recommending the company’s stock to its employees—at the same time that he and other execu- tives were cashing in their shares and bailing out.

Enron’s crash cost the retirement accounts of its employ- ees more than a billion dollars as the company’s stock fell from the stratosphere to only a few pennies a share. Outside

investors lost even more. The reason Enron’s collapse caught investors by surprise—the company’s market value was $28 billion just two months before its bankruptcy—was that Enron had always made its financial records and accounts as opaque as possible. It did this by creating a Byzantine financial structure of off-balance-sheet special- purpose entities—reportedly as many as 9,000—that were supposed to be separate and independent from the main company. Enron’s board of direc-

tors condoned these and other dubious accounting practices and voted twice to permit executives to pursue personal interests that ran contrary to those of the company. When Enron was obliged to redo its financial statements for one three-year period, its profits dropped $600 million and its debts increased $630 million.

SOMETIMES THE RICH AND MIGHTY FALL. Take Kenneth Lay, for example. Convicted by a jury of conspiracy and multiple counts of fraud, he had been chairman and CEO of Enron until that once mighty company took a nose dive and crashed. Founded in the 1980s, Enron soon became a domi- nant player in the field of energy trading, growing rapidly to become America’s seventh biggest company. Wall Street loves growth, and Enron was its darling, ad- mired as dynamic, innovative, and—of course—profitable. Enron stock ex- ploded in value, increasing 40 percent in a single year. The next year it shot up 58 percent and the year after that an unbelievable 89 percent. The fact that nobody could quite understand exactly how the company made its money didn’t seem to matter.

Fortune magazine voted Enron Amer- ica’s “Most Innovative Company” for six consecutive years, and Enron proudly took to calling itself not just “the world’s leading energy com- pany” but also “the world’s leading company.” But when Enron was later forced to declare bankruptcy—at the time the largest Chapter 11 filing in U.S. history—the world learned that its leg- endary financial prowess was illusory and the company’s suc- cess built on the sands of hype. And the hype continued to the

CHApTER 1

The NaTure of Moral iTy

THE REASON ENRON’S

collapse caught investors by surprise . . . was

that Enron had always made its financial

records and accounts as opaque as possible.

Part One | MOral PhilOsOPhy and Business

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 1 03/09/15 4:20 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

2 part one moral philosophy and business

who are compensated according to their ability to bring in and support investment banking deals. Enron was known in the industry as the “deal machine” because it generated so much investment banking business—limited partnerships, loans, and derivatives. That may explain why, only days before Enron filed bankruptcy, just two of the sixteen Wall Street analysts who cov- ered the company recommended that cli- ents sell the stock. The large banks that Enron did business with played a corrupt role, too, by helping manufacture its fraudu- lent financial statements. (Subsequent law- suits have forced them to cough up some

of their profits: Citibank, for example, had to pay Enron’s victimized shareholders $2 billion.) But the rot didn’t stop there. Enron and Andersen enjoyed extensive political connec- tions, which had helped over the years to ensure the passage of a series of deregulatory measures favorable to the energy company. Of the 248 members of Congress sitting on the eleven House and Senate committees charged with investigat- ing Enron’s collapse, 212 had received money from Enron or its accounting firm.1

Stories of business corruption and of greed and wrongdoing in high places have always fascinated the popular press, and media interest in business ethics has never been higher. But one should not be misled by the headlines and news reports. Not all moral issues in business involve giant corporations and their well-heeled executives, and few cases of business ethics are widely publicized. The vast majority of them involve the mundane, uncelebrated moral challenges that working men and women meet daily.

Although the financial shenanigans at Enron were compli- cated, once their basic outline is sketched, the wrongdoing is pretty easy to see: deception, dishonesty, fraud, disregarding one’s professional responsibilities, and unfairly injuring others for one’s own gain. But many of the moral issues that arise in busi- ness are complex and difficult to answer. For example:

How far must manufacturers go to ensure product safety? Must they reveal everything about a product, including any possible defects or shortcomings? At what point does acceptable exaggeration become lying

Still, Enron’s financial auditors should have spotted these and other problems. After all, the shell game Enron was playing is an old one, and months before the company ran aground, Enron Vice President Sherron Watkins had warned Lay that the com- pany could soon “implode in a wave of accounting scandals.” Yet both Arthur Andersen, Enron’s longtime outside auditing firm, and Vinson & Elkins, the company’s law firm, had routinely put together and signed off on various dubious financial deals, and in doing so made large profits for themselves. Arthur Andersen, in particular, was supposed to make sure that the company’s public records reflected financial reality, but Andersen was more wor- ried about its auditing and consulting fees than about its fiduciary responsibilities. Even worse, when the scandal began to break, a partner at Andersen organized the shredding of incriminating Enron documents before investigators could lay their hands on them. As a result, the eighty-nine-year-old accounting firm was convicted of obstructing justice. The Supreme Court later over- turned that verdict on a technicality, but by then Arthur Andersen had already been driven out of business. (The year before Enron went under, by the way, the Securities and Exchange Commission fined Andersen $7 million for approving misleading accounts at Waste Management, and it also had to pay $110 million to settle a lawsuit for auditing work it did for Sunbeam before it, too, filed for bankruptcy. And when massive accounting fraud was later uncovered at WorldCom, it came out that the company’s auditor was—you guessed it—Arthur Andersen.)

Enron’s fall also revealed the conflicts of interest that threaten the credibility of Wall Street’s analysts—analysts

the collapse of Enron’s stock price in late 2001

0 Oct. 16 Oct. 22 Oct. 24 Nov. 28

5

10

15

20

25

30

35

40 $38.44

$20.65

$16.41

$0.61

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 2 03/09/15 4:20 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

chapter one The naTure of moraliTy 3

about a product or a service? When does aggressive marketing become consumer manipulation? Is adver- tising useful and important or deceptive, misleading, and socially detrimental? When are prices unfair or exploitative?

Are corporations obliged to help combat social prob- lems? What are the environmental responsibilities of business, and is it living up to them? Are pollution per- mits a good idea? Is factory farming morally justifiable?

May employers screen potential employees on the basis of lifestyle, physical appearance, or personality tests? What rights do employees have on the job? Under what conditions may they be disciplined or fired? What, if anything, must business do to improve work conditions? When are wages fair? Do unions promote the interests of workers or infringe their rights? When, if ever, is an employee morally required to blow the whistle?

May employees ever use their positions inside an orga- nization to advance their own interests? Is insider trad- ing or the use of privileged information immoral? How much loyalty do workers owe their companies? What say should a business have over the off-the-job activi- ties of its employees? Do drug tests violate their right to privacy?

What constitutes job discrimination, and how far must business go to ensure equality of opportunity? Is affir- mative action a matter of justice, or a poor idea? How

should organizations respond to the problem of sexual harassment?

LEARNING ObjECTIvES

These questions typify business issues with moral significance. The answers we give to them are determined, in large part, by our moral standards—that is, by the moral principles and values we accept. What moral standards are, where they come from, and how they can be assessed are some of the concerns of this opening chapter. In particular, you will encounter the fol- lowing topics:

1. The nature, scope, and purpose of business ethics

2. The distinguishing features of morality and how it differs from etiquette, law, and professional codes of conduct

3. The relationship between morality and religion

4. The doctrine of ethical relativism and its difficulties

5. What it means to have moral principles; the nature of conscience; and the relationship between morality and self-interest

6. The place of values and ideals in a person’s life

7. The social and psychological factors that sometimes jeopardize an individual’s integrity

8. The characteristics of sound moral reasoning

• • •

e Thics Ethics (or moral philosophy) is a broad field of inquiry that addresses a fundamental query that all of us, at least from time to time, inevitably think about—namely, how should I live my life? that question, of course, leads to others, such as: What sort of person should I strive to be? What values are important? What standards or principles should I live by? exploring these issues immerses one in the study of right and wrong. among other things, moral philosophers and others who think seriously about ethics want to understand the nature of morality, the meaning of its basic concepts, the charac- teristics of good moral reasoning, how moral judgments can be justified, and, of course, the principles or properties that distinguish right actions from wrong actions. thus, ethics deals with individual character and with the moral rules that govern and limit our conduct. It investigates questions of right and wrong, fairness and unfairness, good and

SuMMARY Ethics deals with

individual character and the moral rules

that govern and limit our conduct.

It investigates questions of right

and wrong, duty and obligation, and moral

responsibility.

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 3 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

4 part one moral philosophy and business

bad, duty and obligation, and justice and injustice, as well as moral responsibility and the values that should guide our actions.

You sometimes hear it said that there’s a difference between a person’s ethics and his or her morals. this can be confusing because what some people mean by saying that something is a matter of ethics (as opposed to morals) is often what other people mean by saying that it is a matter of morals (and not ethics). In fact, however, most people (and most philosophers) see no real distinction between a person’s “morals” and a person’s “ethics.” and almost everyone uses “ethical” and “moral” interchangeably to describe people we consider good and actions we consider right, and “unethical” and “immoral” to designate bad people and wrong actions. this book follows that common usage.

Business and OrganizatiOnal ethics

the primary focus of this book is ethics as it applies to business. business ethics is the study of what constitutes right and wrong, or good and bad, human conduct in a business context. For example, would it be right for a store manager to break a promise to a cus- tomer and sell some hard-to-find merchandise to someone else, whose need for it is greater? What, if anything, should a moral employee do when his or her superiors refuse to look into apparent wrongdoing in a branch office? If you innocently came across secret informa- tion about a competitor, would it be permissible for you to use it for your own advantage?

recent business scandals have renewed the interest of business leaders, academics, and society at large in ethics. For example, the association to advance collegiate Schools of Business, which comprises all the top business schools, has introduced new rules on including ethics in their curricula, and in recent years thousands of MBa students have signed the “MBa oath,” a voluntary pledge to “not advance my personal interests at the expense of my enterprise or society,” to “refrain from corruption, unfair competition, or business practices harmful to society,” and to “protect the human rights and dignity of all people affected by my enterprise.”2 But an appreciation of the importance of ethics for a healthy society and a concern, in particular, for what constitutes ethical conduct in business go back to ancient times. the roman philosopher cicero (106–43 bce), for instance, discussed the example, much debated at the time, of an honest merchant from alexandria who brings a large stock of wheat to rhodes where there is a food shortage. on his way there, he learns that other traders are setting sail for rhodes with substantial cargos of grain. Should he tell the people of rhodes that more wheat is on the way, or say nothing and sell at the best price he can? Some ancient ethicists argued that although the merchant must declare defects in his wares as required by law, as a vendor he is free— provided he tells no untruths—to sell his goods as profitably as he can. others, including cicero, argued to the contrary that all the facts must be revealed and that buyers must be as fully informed as sellers.3

“Business” and “businessperson” are broad terms. a “business” could be a food truck or a multinational corporation that operates in several countries. “Businessperson” could refer to a street vendor or a company president responsible for thousands of workers and millions of shareholder dollars. accordingly, the word business will be used here sim- ply to mean any organization whose objective is to provide goods or services for profit. businesspeople are those who participate in planning, organizing, or directing the work of business.

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 4 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

chapter one The naTure of moraliTy 5

But this book takes a broader view as well because it is concerned with moral issues that arise wherever employers and employees come together. thus, it addresses organi- zational ethics as well as business ethics. an organization is a group of people working together to achieve a common purpose. the purpose may be to offer a product or a service primarily for profit, as in business. But the purpose also could be health care, as in medical organizations; public safety and order, as in law enforcement organizations; education, as in academic organizations; and so on. the cases and illustrations presented in this book deal with moral issues and dilemmas in both business and nonbusiness orga- nizational settings.

people occasionally poke fun at the idea of business ethics, declaring that the term is a contradiction or that business has no ethics. Such people take themselves to be worldly and realistic. they think they have a down-to-earth idea of how things really work. In fact, despite its pretense of sophistication, their attitude shows little grasp of the nature of ethics and only a superficial understanding of the real world of business. reading this book should help you comprehend how inaccurate and mistaken their view is.

• • •

Mor al V ersus NoNMor al sTaNda rds Moral questions differ from other kinds of questions. Whether the old computer in your office can copy a pirated DVD is a factual question. By contrast, whether you should copy the DVD is a moral question. When we answer a moral question or make a moral judg- ment, we appeal to moral standards. these standards differ from other kinds of standards.

Wearing shorts and a tank top to a formal dinner party is boorish behavior. Writing an essay that is filled with double negatives or lacks subject–verb agreement violates the basic conventions of proper language usage. photographing someone at night without the flash turned on is a poor photographic technique. In each case a standard is violated— fashion, grammatical, technical—but the violation does not pose a serious threat to human well-being.

Moral standards are different because they concern behavior that is of serious consequence to human welfare, that can profoundly injure or benefit people.4 the con- ventional moral norms against lying, stealing, and killing deal with actions that can hurt people. and the moral principle that human beings should be treated with dignity and respect uplifts the human personality. Whether products are healthful or harmful, work conditions safe or dangerous, personnel procedures biased or fair, privacy respected or invaded––these are also matters that seriously affect human well-being. the standards that govern our conduct in these areas are moral standards.

a second characteristic follows from the first. Moral standards take priority over other standards, including self-interest. Something that morality condemns—for instance, the burglary of your neighbor’s home—cannot be justified on the nonmoral grounds that it would be a thrill to do it or that it would pay off handsomely. We take moral stan- dards to be more important than other considerations in guiding our actions.

a third characteristic of moral standards is that their soundness depends on the ade- quacy of the reasons that support or justify them. For the most part, fashion standards are set by clothing designers, merchandisers, and consumers; grammatical standards by

SuMMARY Business ethics is the study of

what constitutes right and wrong

(or good and bad) human conduct in

a business context. Closely related moral

questions arise in other organizational

contexts.

Moral standards concern behavior that seriously affects human well-being.

Moral standards take priority over other standards.

The soundness of moral standards depends on the adequacy of the reasons that support them.

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 5 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

6 part one moral philosophy and business

grammarians and students of language; technical standards by practitioners and experts in the field. Legislators make laws, boards of directors make organizational policy, and licensing boards establish standards for professionals. In those cases, some authoritative body is the ultimate validating source of the standards and thus can change the standards if it wishes. Moral standards are not made by such bodies. their validity depends not on official fiat but rather on the quality of the arguments or the reasoning that supports them. exactly what constitutes adequate grounds or justification for a moral standard is a debated question, which, as we shall see in chapter 2, underlies disagreement among philosophers over which specific moral principles are best.

although these three characteristics set moral standards apart from other standards, it is useful to discuss more specifically how morality differs from three things with which it is sometimes confused: etiquette, law, and professional codes of ethics.

MOrality and etiquette

Etiquette refers to the norms of correct conduct in polite society or, more generally, to any special code of social behavior or courtesy. In our society, for example, it is consid- ered bad etiquette to chew with your mouth open or to pick your nose when talking to someone; it is considered good etiquette to say “please” when requesting and “thank you” when receiving, and to hold a door open for someone entering immediately behind you. Good business etiquette typically calls for writing follow-up letters after meetings, returning phone calls, and dressing appropriately. It is commonplace to judge people’s manners as “good” or “bad” and the conduct that reflects them as “right” or “wrong.” “Good,” “bad,” “right,” and “wrong” here simply mean socially appropriate or socially inappropriate. In these contexts, such words express judgments about manners, not about ethics.

the rules of etiquette are prescriptions for socially acceptable behavior. If you violate them, you’re likely to be considered ill-mannered, impolite, or even uncivilized, but not necessarily immoral. If you want to fit in, get along with others, and be thought well of by them, you should observe the common rules of politeness or etiquette. however, what’s considered correct or polite conduct—for example, when greeting an elderly person, when using your knife and fork, or when determining how close to stand to someone you’re conversing with—can change over time and vary from society to society.

although rules of etiquette are generally nonmoral in character, violations of those rules can have moral implications. For example, the male boss who refers to female sub- ordinates as “honey” or “doll” shows bad manners. If such epithets diminish the worth of female employees or perpetuate sexism, then they also raise moral issues concerning equal treatment and denial of dignity to human beings. More generally, rude or impolite con- duct can be offensive, and it may sometimes fail to show the respect for other persons that morality requires of us. For this reason, it is important to exercise care, in business situations and elsewhere, when dealing with unfamiliar customs or people from a different culture.

Scrupulous observance of rules of etiquette, however, does not make a person moral. In fact, it can sometimes camouflage ethical issues. In some parts of the United States sixty years ago, it was considered bad manners for blacks and whites to eat together. however, those who obeyed this convention were not acting in a morally desirable way. In the 1960s, black and white members of the civil rights movement sought to dramatize the injustice that lay behind this rule by sitting together in luncheonettes and

SuMMARY We appeal to moral

standards when we answer a moral question or make a moral judgment.

Three characteristics of moral standards distinguish them

from other kinds of standards.

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 6 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

chapter one The naTure of moraliTy 7

restaurants. although judged at the time to lack good manners, they thought that this was a small price to pay for exposing the unequal treatment and human degradation underlying this rule of etiquette.

MOrality and law

Before distinguishing between morality and law, let’s examine the term law. Basically, there are four kinds of law: statutes, regulations, common law, and constitutional law.

Statutes are laws enacted by legislative bodies. For example, the law that defines and prohibits reckless driving on the highway is a statute. congress and state legislatures enact statutes. (Laws enacted by local governing bodies such as city councils are usually termed ordinances.) Statutes make up a large part of the law and are what many of us mean when we speak of “laws.”

Limited in their time and knowledge, legislatures often set up boards or agencies whose functions include issuing detailed regulations covering certain kinds of conduct— administrative regulations. For example, state legislatures establish licensing boards to formulate regulations for the licensing of physicians and nurses. as long as these regula- tions do not exceed the board’s statutory powers and do not conflict with other kinds of law, they are legally binding.

Common law refers to the body of judge-made law that first developed in the english-speaking world centuries ago when there were few statutes. courts frequently wrote opinions explaining the bases of their decisions in specific cases, including the legal principles those decisions rested on. each of these opinions became a precedent for later decisions in similar cases. the massive body of precedents and legal principles that accumulated over the years is collectively referred to as “common law.” Like administra- tive regulations, common law is valid if it harmonizes with statutory law and with still another kind: constitutional law.

Constitutional law refers to court rulings on the requirements of the constitution and the constitutionality of legislation. the U.S. constitution empowers the courts to decide whether laws are compatible with the constitution. State courts may also rule on the constitutionality of state laws under state constitutions. although the courts cannot make laws, they have far-reaching powers to rule on the constitutionality of laws and to declare them invalid if they conflict with the constitution. In the United States, the Supreme court has the greatest judiciary power and rules on an array of cases, some of which bear directly on the study of business ethics.

people sometimes confuse legality and morality, but they are different things. on one hand, breaking the law is not always or necessarily immoral. on the other hand, the legality of an action does not guarantee that it is morally right. Let’s consider these points further.

1. An action can be illegal but morally right. For example, helping a Jewish family to hide from the nazis was against German law in 1939, but it would have been a morally admirable thing to have done. of course, the nazi regime was vicious and evil. By contrast, in a democratic society with a basically just legal order, the fact that something is illegal provides a moral consideration against doing it. For example, one moral reason for not burning trash in your backyard is that it vio- lates an ordinance that your community has voted in favor of. Some philosophers believe that sometimes the illegality of an action can make it morally wrong, even

Legality should not be confused with morality. Breaking the law isn’t always or necessarily immoral, and the legality of an action doesn’t guarantee its morality.

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 7 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

8 part one moral philosophy and business

if the action would otherwise have been morally acceptable. But even if they are right about that, the fact that something is illegal does not trump all other moral considerations. nonconformity to law is not always immoral, even in a democratic society. there can be circumstances where, all things considered, violating the law is morally permissible, perhaps even morally required.

probably no one in the modern era has expressed this point more eloquently than Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr. confined in the Birmingham, alabama, city jail on charges of parading without a permit, King penned his now famous “Letter from Birmingham Jail” to eight of his fellow clergymen who had published a statement attacking King’s unauthorized protest of racial segregation as unwise and untimely. King wrote:

all segregation statutes are unjust because segregation distorts the soul and damages the personality. It gives the segregator a false sense of superiority and the segregated a false sense of inferiority. Segregation, to use the terminology of the Jewish philoso- pher Martin Buber, substitutes an “I-it” relationship for an “I-thou” relationship and ends up relegating persons to the status of things. hence segregation is not only politically, economically, and sociologically unsound, it is morally wrong and sinful. . . . thus it is that I can urge men to obey the 1954 decision of the Supreme court,* for it is morally right; and I can urge them to disobey segregation ordi nances, for they are morally wrong.5

2. An action that is legal can be morally wrong. For example, brokers are not legally required to act in their customers’ best interests, even when they are advising them on their retirement money.6 Yet it would be wrong of them to push their clients into investments that are bad for them in order to reap a commission. Likewise, it may have been perfectly legal for the chairman of a profitable company to lay off 125 workers and use three-quarters of the money saved to boost his pay and that of the company’s other top managers,7 but the morality of his doing so is open to debate.

or, to take another example, suppose that you’re driving to work one day and see an accident victim sitting on the side of the road, clearly in shock and needing medical assistance. Because you know first aid and are in no great hurry to get to your destination, you could easily stop and assist the person. Legally speaking, though, you are not obligated to stop and render aid. Under common law, the prudent thing would be to drive on, because by stopping you could thus incur legal liability if you fail to exercise reasonable care and thereby injure the person. Many states have enacted so-called Good Samaritan laws to provide immunity from damages to those rendering aid (except for gross negligence or serious misconduct). But in most states, the law does not oblige people to give such aid or even to call an ambulance. Moral theorists would agree, however, that if you sped away without helping or even calling for help, your action might be perfectly legal but would be morally suspect. regardless of the law, such conduct would almost certainly be wrong.

What then may we say about the relationship between law and morality? to a signif- icant extent, law codifies a society’s customs, ideals, norms, and moral values. changes in

*In Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka (1954), the Supreme court struck down the half-century-old “separate but equal doctrine,” which permitted racially segregated schools as long as comparable quality was maintained.

SuMMARY Morality must be

distinguished from etiquette (rules for

well-mannered behavior), from law

(statutes, regulations, common law,

and constitutional law), and from

professional codes of ethics (the special

rules governing the members of a

profession).

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 8 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

chapter one The naTure of moraliTy 9

law tend to reflect changes in what a society takes to be right and wrong, but sometimes changes in the law can alter people’s ideas about the rightness or wrongness of conduct. however, even if a society’s laws are sensible and morally sound, it is a mistake to see them as sufficient to establish the moral standards that should guide us. the law cannot cover all possible human conduct, and in many situations it is too blunt an instrument to provide adequate moral guidance. the law generally prohibits egregious affronts to a society’s moral standards and in that sense is the “floor” of moral conduct, but breaches of moral conduct can slip through cracks in that floor.

PrOfessiOnal cOdes

Somewhere between etiquette and law lie professional codes of ethics. these are the rules that are supposed to govern the conduct of members of a given profession. adhering to these rules is a required part of membership in that profession. Violation of a professional code may result in the disapproval of one’s professional peers and, in serious cases, loss of one’s license to practice that profession. Sometimes these codes are unwrit- ten and are part of the common understanding of members of a particular profession— for example, that professors should not date their students. In other instances, these codes or portions of them may be written down by an authoritative body so they may be better taught and more efficiently enforced.

these written rules are sometimes so vague and general as to be of little value, and often they amount to little more than self-promotion by the professional organization. the same is frequently true when industries or corporations publish statements of their ethical standards. In other cases—for example, with attorneys—professional codes can be very specific and detailed. It is difficult to generalize about the content of professional codes of ethics, however, because they frequently involve a mix of purely moral rules (for

You come upon this scene—the car is smoking, and it is clear that an accident just took place. In most states, you are not legally obligated to stop and offer help to the victims.

© M

ik ad

un /S

hu tte

rs to

ck .c

om

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 9 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

10 part one moral philosophy and business

example, client confidentiality), of professional etiquette (for example, the billing of ser- vices to other professionals), and of restrictions intended to benefit the group’s economic interests (for example, limitations on price competition).

Given their nature, professional codes of ethics are neither a complete nor a com- pletely reliable guide to one’s moral obligations. not all the rules of a professional code are purely moral in character, and even when they are, the fact that a rule is officially enshrined as part of the code of a profession does not guarantee that it is a sound moral principle. as a professional, you must take seriously the injunctions of your profession, but you still have the responsibility to critically assess those rules for yourself.

regarding those parts of the code that concern etiquette or financial matters, bear in mind that by joining a profession you are probably agreeing, explicitly or implicitly, to abide by those standards. assuming that those rules don’t require morally impermissible conduct, then consenting to them gives you some moral obligation to follow them. In addition, for many, living up to the standards of one’s chosen profession is an important source of personal satisfaction. Still, you must be alert to situations in which professional standards or customary professional practice conflicts with ordinary ethical require- ments. adherence to a professional code does not exempt your conduct from scrutiny from the broader perspective of morality.

where dO MOral standards cOMe frOM?

So far you have seen how moral standards are different from various nonmoral standards, but you probably wonder about the source of those moral standards. Most, if not all, people have certain moral principles or a moral code that they explicitly or implicitly accept. Because the moral principles of different people in the same society overlap, at least in part, we can also talk about the moral code of a society, meaning the moral standards shared by its members. how do we come to have certain moral principles and not others? obviously, many things influence what moral principles we accept: our early upbringing, the behavior of those around us, the explicit and implicit standards of our culture, our own experiences, and our critical reflections on those experiences.

For philosophers, though, the central question is not how we came to have the particular principles we have. the philosophical issue is whether those principles can be justified. Do we simply take for granted the values of those around us? or, like Martin Luther King, Jr., are we able to think independently about moral matters? By analogy, we pick up our nonmoral beliefs from all sorts of sources: books, conversations with friends, movies, various experiences we’ve had. What is important, however, is not how we acquired the beliefs we have, but whether or to what extent those beliefs—for example, that women are more emotional than men or that telekinesis is possible—can withstand critical scrutiny. Likewise, ethical theories attempt to justify moral standards and ethical beliefs. the next chapter examines some of the major theories of normative ethics. It looks at what some of the major thinkers in human history have argued are the best-justified standards of right and wrong.

But first we need to consider the relationship between morality and religion on the one hand and between morality and society on the other. Some people main- tain that morality just boils down to religion. others have argued for the doctrine of ethical relativism, which says that right and wrong are only a function of what a particular society takes to be right and wrong. Both those views are mistaken.

You should take seriously the code that

governs your profession, but you still have a

responsibility to assess its rules for yourself.

For philosophers, the important issue is

not where our moral principles came from, but whether they can

be justified.

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 10 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

chapter one The naTure of moraliTy 11

• • •

rel ig ioN aNd Mor al iT y any religion provides its believers with a worldview, part of which involves certain moral instructions, values, and commitments. the Jewish and christian traditions, to name just two, offer a view of humans as unique products of a divine intervention that has endowed them with consciousness and an ability to love. Both these traditions posit creatures who stand midway between nature and spirit. on one hand, we are finite and bound to earth, not only capable of wrongdoing but also born morally flawed (original sin). on the other, we can transcend nature and realize infinite possibilities.

primarily because of the influence of Western religion, many americans and others view themselves as beings with a supernatural destiny, as possessing a life after death, as being immortal. one’s purpose in life is found in serving and loving God. For the christian, the way to serve and love God is by emulating the life of Jesus of nazareth. In the life of Jesus, christians find an expression of the highest virtue—love. they love when they perform selfless acts, develop a keen social conscience, and realize that human beings are creatures of God and therefore intrinsically worthwhile. For the Jew, one serves and loves God chiefly through expressions of justice and righteousness. Jews also develop a sense of honor derived from a commitment to truth, humility, fidelity, and kindness. this commitment hones their sense of responsibility to family and community.

religion, then, involves not only a formal system of worship but also prescriptions for social relationships. one example is the mandate “Do unto others as you would have them do unto you.” termed the “Golden rule,” this injunction represents one of humankind’s highest moral ideals and can be found in essence in all the great religions of the world:

Good people proceed while considering that what is best for others is best for themselves. (Hitopadesa, hinduism)

thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself. (Leviticus 19:18, Judaism)

therefore all things whatsoever ye would that men should do to you, do ye even so to them. (Matthew 7:12, christianity)

hurt not others with that which pains yourself. (Udanavarga 5:18, Buddhism)

What you do not want done to yourself, do not do to others. (Analects 15:23, confucianism)

no one of you is a believer until he loves for his brother what he loves for himself. (Traditions, Islam)

although inspiring, such religious ideals are very general and can be difficult to translate into precise policy injunctions. religious bodies, nevertheless, occasionally articulate positions on more specific political, educational, economic, and medical issues, which help mold public opinion on matters as diverse as abortion, the environment, national defense, and the ethics of scientific research. roman catholicism, in particular, has a rich history of formally applying its core values to the moral aspects of industrial

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 11 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

12 part one moral philosophy and business

relations and economic life. pope Francis’s 2013 apostolic exhortation, “the Gospel of Joy,” stands in that tradition. there and elsewhere, the pope has rejected an “economy of exclusion” and criticized blind faith in a free market that perpetuates inequality—a mes- sage that some politicians in Washington are starting to listen to.8

MOrality needn’t rest On religiOn

Many people believe that morality must be based on religion, either in the sense that without religion people would have no incentive to be moral or in the sense that only religion can provide moral guidance. others contend that morality is based on the com- mands of God. none of these claims is convincing.

First, although a desire to avoid hell and to go to heaven may prompt some of us to act morally, this is not the only reason or even the most common reason that people behave morally. often we act morally out of habit or just because that is the kind of per- son we are. It would simply not occur to most of us to swipe an elderly lady’s purse, and if the idea did occur to us, we wouldn’t do it because such an act simply doesn’t fit with our personal standards or with our concept of ourselves. We are often motivated to do what is morally right out of concern for others or just because it is right. In addition, the approval of our peers, the need to appease our conscience, and the desire to avoid earthly punishment may all motivate us to act morally. Furthermore, atheists generally live lives as moral and upright as those of believers.

Second, the moral instructions of the world’s great religions are general and impre- cise: they do not relieve us of the necessity of engaging in moral reasoning ourselves. For example, the Bible says, “thou shall not kill.” Yet christians disagree among themselves over the morality of fighting in wars, of capital punishment, of killing in self-defense, of slaughtering animals, of abortion and euthanasia, and of allowing foreigners to die from famine because we have not provided them with as much food as we might have. the Bible does not provide unambiguous solutions to these moral problems, so even believers must engage in moral philosophy if they are to have intelligent answers. on the other hand, there are lots of reasons for believing that, say, a cold-blooded murder motivated by greed is immoral. You don’t have to believe in a religion to figure that out.

Third, although some theologians have advocated the divine command theory— that if something is wrong (like killing an innocent person for fun), then the only reason it is wrong is that God commands us not to do it—many theologians and certainly most philosophers would reject this view. they would contend that if God commands human beings not to do something, such as commit rape, it is because God sees that rape is wrong, but it is not God’s forbidding rape that makes it wrong. the fact that rape is wrong is independent of God’s decrees.

Most believers think not only that God gives us moral instructions or rules but also that God has moral reasons for giving them to us. according to the divine command theory, this would make no sense. In this view, there is no reason that something is right or wrong, other than the fact that it is God’s will. all believers, of course, believe that God is good and that God commands us to do what is right and forbids us to do what is wrong. But this doesn’t mean, say critics of the divine command theory, that it is God’s saying so that makes a thing wrong, any more than it is your mother’s telling you not to steal that makes it wrong to steal.

The idea that morality must be based

on religion can be interpreted in three

different ways, none of which is very plausible.

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 12 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

chapter one The naTure of moraliTy 13

all this is simply to argue that morality is not necessarily based on religion in any of these three senses. that religion influences the moral standards and values of most of us is beyond doubt. But given that religions differ in their moral beliefs and that even members of the same faith often disagree on moral matters, you cannot justify a moral judgment simply by appealing to religion—for that will only persuade those who already agree with your particular interpretation of your particular religion. Besides, most religions hold that human reason is capable of understanding what is right and wrong, so it is human reason to which you will have to appeal in order to support your ethical principles and judgments.

• • •

e Th ical rel aT iV isM Some people do not believe that morality boils down to religion but rather that it is merely a function of what a particular society happens to believe. this view is called ethical relativism, the theory that what is right is determined by what a culture or soci- ety says is right. What is right in one place may be wrong in another, because the only criterion for distinguishing right from wrong—and so the only ethical standard for judg- ing an action—is the moral system of the society in which the act occurs.

abortion, for example, is condemned as immoral in catholic Ireland but is prac- ticed as a morally neutral form of birth control in Japan. according to the ethical relativ- ist, then, abortion is wrong in Ireland but morally permissible in Japan. the relativist is not saying merely that the Irish believe abortion is abominable and the Japanese do not; that is acknowledged by everyone. rather, the ethical relativist contends that abortion is immoral in Ireland because the Irish believe it to be immoral and that it is morally permissible in Japan because the Japanese believe it to be so. thus, for the ethical relativ- ist there is no absolute ethical standard independent of cultural context, no criterion of right and wrong by which to judge other than that of particular societies. In short, what morality requires is relative to society.

those who endorse ethical relativism point to the apparent diversity of human values and the multiformity of moral codes to support their case. From our own cul- tural perspective, some seemingly immoral moralities have been adopted. polygamy, pedophilia, stealing, slavery, infanticide, and cannibalism have all been tolerated or even encouraged by the moral system of one society or another. In light of this fact, the ethi- cal relativist believes that there can be no non-ethnocentric standard by which to judge actions.

Some thinkers believe that the moral differences between societies are smaller and less significant than they appear. they contend that variations in moral standards reflect differing factual beliefs and differing circumstances rather than fundamental differences in values. But suppose they are wrong about this matter. the relativist’s conclusion still does not follow. a difference of opinion among societies about right and wrong no more proves that none of the conflicting beliefs is true or superior to the others than the diversity of viewpoints expressed in a college seminar establishes that there is no truth. In short, disagreement in ethical matters does not imply that all opinions are equally correct.

SuMMARY Morality is not

necessarily based on religion. Although

we draw our moral beliefs from many sources, for philosophers the issue is whether

those beliefs can be justified.

Ethical disagreement does not imply that all opinions are equally correct.

82088_ch01_ptg01_001-042.indd 13 03/09/15 4:21 PM

Copyright 2017 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights, some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materially affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.

14 part one moral philosophy and business

Moreover, ethical relativism has some unsatisfactory implications. First, it under- mines any moral criticism of the practices of other societies as long as their actions con- form to their own standards. We cannot say that slavery in a slave society like that of the american South 175 years ago was immoral and unjust as long as that society held it to be morally permissible.

Second, and closely related, is the fact that for the relativist there is no such thing as ethical progress. although moralities may change, they cannot get better or worse. thus, we cannot say that moral standards today are more enlightened than were moral stan- dards in the Middle ages.

Third, from the relativist’s point of view, it makes no sense for people to criticize principles or practices accepted by their own society. people can be censured for not living up to their society’s moral code, but that is all. the moral code itself cannot be criticized because whatever a society takes to be right really is right for it. reformers who identify injustices in their society and campaign against them are only encouraging peo- ple to be immoral—that is, to depart from the moral standards of their society—unless or until the majority of the society agrees with the reformers. the minority can never be right in moral matters; to be right it must become the majority.

the ethical relativist is correct to emphasize that in viewing other cultures we should keep an open mind and not simply dismiss alien social practices on the basis of our own cultural prejudices. But the relativist’s theory of morality doesn’t hold up. the more carefully we examine it, the less plausible it becomes. there is no good reason for saying that the majority view on moral issues is automatically right, and the belief that it is auto- matically right has unacceptable consequences.

relativisM and the “gaMe” Of Business

In his essay “Is Business Bluffing ethical?” albert carr argues that business, as practiced by individuals as well as by corporations, has the impersonal character of a game—a game that demands both special strategy and an understanding of its special ethical standards.9 Business has its own norms and rules that differ from those of the rest of society. thus, according to carr, a number of things that we normally think of as wrong are really permissible in a business context. his examples include conscious misstatement and con- cealment of pertinent facts in negotiation, lying about one’s age on a résumé, deceptive packaging, automobile companies’ neglect of car safety, and utility companies’ manipula- tion of regulators and overcharging of electricity users. he draws an analogy with poker:

poker’s own brand of ethics is different from the ethical ideals of civilized human relationships. the game calls for distrust of the other fellow. It ignores the claim of friendship. cunning deception and concealment of one’s strength and intentions, not kindness and openheartedness, are vital in poker. no one thinks any the worse of poker on that account. and no one should think any the worse of the game of busi- ness because its standards of right and wrong differ from the prevailing traditions of morality in our society.10

What carr is defending here is a kind of ethical relativism: Business has its own moral standards, and business actions should be evaluated only by those standards.

one can argue whether carr has accurately identified the implicit rules of the business world (for example, is misrepresentation on one’s résumé really a permissible

Homework is Completed By:

Writer Writer Name Amount Client Comments & Rating
Instant Homework Helper

ONLINE

Instant Homework Helper

$36

She helped me in last minute in a very reasonable price. She is a lifesaver, I got A+ grade in my homework, I will surely hire her again for my next assignments, Thumbs Up!

Order & Get This Solution Within 3 Hours in $25/Page

Custom Original Solution And Get A+ Grades

  • 100% Plagiarism Free
  • Proper APA/MLA/Harvard Referencing
  • Delivery in 3 Hours After Placing Order
  • Free Turnitin Report
  • Unlimited Revisions
  • Privacy Guaranteed

Order & Get This Solution Within 6 Hours in $20/Page

Custom Original Solution And Get A+ Grades

  • 100% Plagiarism Free
  • Proper APA/MLA/Harvard Referencing
  • Delivery in 6 Hours After Placing Order
  • Free Turnitin Report
  • Unlimited Revisions
  • Privacy Guaranteed

Order & Get This Solution Within 12 Hours in $15/Page

Custom Original Solution And Get A+ Grades

  • 100% Plagiarism Free
  • Proper APA/MLA/Harvard Referencing
  • Delivery in 12 Hours After Placing Order
  • Free Turnitin Report
  • Unlimited Revisions
  • Privacy Guaranteed

6 writers have sent their proposals to do this homework:

Engineering Help
Assignment Solver
Homework Master
Finance Homework Help
Top Class Engineers
Academic Master
Writer Writer Name Offer Chat
Engineering Help

ONLINE

Engineering Help

I have read and understood all your initial requirements, and I am very professional in this task.

$39 Chat With Writer
Assignment Solver

ONLINE

Assignment Solver

I am known as Unrivaled Quality, Written to Standard, providing Plagiarism-free woork, and Always on Time

$43 Chat With Writer
Homework Master

ONLINE

Homework Master

Give me a chance, i will do this with my best efforts

$43 Chat With Writer
Finance Homework Help

ONLINE

Finance Homework Help

Hello, I an ranked top 10 freelancers in academic and contents writing. I can write and updated your personal statement with great quality and free of plagiarism

$42 Chat With Writer
Top Class Engineers

ONLINE

Top Class Engineers

I am known as Unrivaled Quality, Written to Standard, providing Plagiarism-free woork, and Always on Time

$35 Chat With Writer
Academic Master

ONLINE

Academic Master

I have read your project details. I can do this within your deadline.

$37 Chat With Writer

Let our expert academic writers to help you in achieving a+ grades in your homework, assignment, quiz or exam.

Similar Homework Questions

DFTT week14 DB - Saudamini joshi datta bavani - Uniform gradient present worth excel - Reading summary - Angular momentum of a rotating rod - Analytical techniques in biochemistry - Film study guide the wizard of oz answers - Cloud computing thomas erl pdf - Environmental planning sample quiz 3 - Bowenian family therapy concepts - Attic red figure kylix - Novice to expert theory patricia benner - Imb reward saver account - Rotated component matrix spss - Determination of an equilibrium constant lab conclusion - Trakia journal of sciences - The big risk of employing an outsourcing strategy is - Practical Connection Paper- Deadline 2hours -$5 - How to use autodesk remake - Faust prologue in heaven - Introduction to shakespeare sonnets - Should everyone go to college they say i say - Dr chris conradie cardiologist - Research papers on virtualization in cloud computing - Budget variance analysis excel - Linux cheat sheet shirt - Discussion: Professional Nursing and State-Level Regulations,NURS 6050 Policy and Advocacy for Improving Population Health - Relatively prime to n - Inside intel inside case study solution - Baking soda vinegar balanced equation - Discition - Reply needed - Acu atar cut offs 2016 - Jack bondurant family tree - Murdoch university census date - Blue collar brilliance summary and response - Impartial language in writing - 12/70 park street st kilda west - Logic gate truth tables - Hospital continuity of operations plan example - Japanese culture essay - Advance Phisyology (Due 2 hours) - Cape town census 2011 - Grtep webcom 2.0 - O bid me leap - Taylormade r540 xd driver illegal - Referee Report - As 1905.1 fire doors - Njb basketball las vegas - What does 100 overall match mean on safeassign - Terzaghi and peck 1967 - Post modified noun phrase - How to separate wood shavings from sand - Fema emergency management institute answers - John and judy goolsby elementary - Discussion: Combination of IOT with AI in determining consumer behavior based energy wastage - Short essay on garbage collector - Moral of the road not taken - Business and its environment 6th edition - Claudette nevins cause of death - Continued work extend 3 more pages ... - Walter dolhare wells fargo - In ______________ on their first missionary journey, paul and barnabas were mistaken for gods. - 2 page paper - Actuarial mathematics for life contingent risks 2nd edition pdf - Strange lines vertical and horizontal homework answer key - Assignment 2 social control and criminal deviance bullying - Anthony kiedis personality type - Ultra micro gas turbine - Ochre restaurant cairns menu - Cisco packet tracer add simple pdu - Criteria for weighted scoring model - Jb hi fi rangehoods - Lorem, ipsum - Seal skin wetsuits penrith - Organization leadership and decision making - Casein glue lab answers - A shopping bot is one of the simplest examples of an intelligent agent. - Collective Bargaining Case Study - Mmu counselling drop in - Marketing analytics case study pdf - War of independence 1857 pakistan studies notes - Components of cloud computing ppt - Describe the criteria for classifying leases by a lessee - Woolworths share buy back - Week 3 - Billy goats gruff troll - All else being equal socially responsible firms - SELECTION PROCESS - Plumpton college veterinary nursing - Bill gates leadership style theory - Darius arya ancestry - Investigation procedures and techniques - HR_GLOB_FIN (U2_RPLx2) - The unit contribution margin is computed by mcq - Inputs strategic plans target elements of change and outputs - A completely amorphous and nonporous polymer will be - How does design affect readability course hero - Animal habitat poster project - How to track gautrain bus