Philosophy Paper
article to write about: https://www.procon.org/headline.php?headlineID=005323
When looking for information about a particular issue, how often do you try to resist biases toward your own point of view? This assignment asks you to engage in this aspect of critical thinking by playing the “Believing Game.” The Believing Game is about making the effort to "believe” – or at least consider – the reasons for an opposing view on an issue.
In this assignment, you will first read a book excerpt about critical thinking processes: "The Believing Game and How to Make Conflicting Opinions More Fruitful" at http://www.procon.org/sourcefiles/believinggame.pdf. Next, you will review the Procon.org Website in order to gather information. Then, you will engage in prewriting to examine your thoughts.
Note: In Part II of the assignment (due Week 4), you will write an essay geared towards synthesizing your ideas.
Follow the instructions below for this activity. Use complete sentences and adhere to standard rules of English grammar, punctuation, mechanics, and spelling.
Select one (1) of the approved topics from the www.procon.org Website and state your position on the issue.
From the Procon.org Website, identify three (3) premises (reasons) listed under either the Pro or Con section -- whichever section opposes your position.
For each of the three (3) premises (reasons) that oppose your position on the issue, answer these “believing” questions suggested by Elbow:
What's interesting or helpful about this view?
What would I notice if I believed this view?
In what sense or under what conditions might this idea be true?"
The paper should follow guidelines for clear and organized writing:
Include an introductory paragraph and concluding paragraph.
Address main ideas in body paragraphs with a topic sentence and supporting sentences.
Adhere to standard rules of English grammar, punctuation, mechanics, and spelling.
Your assignment must follow these formatting requirements:
Be typed, double spaced, using Times New Roman font (size 12), with one-inch margins on all sides; citations and references must follow APA Style format. Check with your professor for any additional instructions.
Include a cover page containing the title of the assignment, the student’s name, the professor’s name, the course title, and the date. The cover page and the reference page are not included in the required assignment page length.
The specific course learning outcomes associated with this assignment are:
Create written work utilizing the concepts of critical thinking.
Use technology and information resources to research issues in critical thinking skills and informal logic.
Criteria
Unacceptable
Below 60% F
Meets Minimum Expectations
60-69% D
Fair
70-79% C
Proficient
80-89% B
Exemplary
90-100% A
1. Select one (1) of the approved topics from the www.procon.org Website and state your position on the issue.
Weight: 20%
Did not submit or incompletely selected one (1) of the approved topics from the www.procon.org Website; did not submit or incompletely stated your position on the issue.
Insufficiently selected one (1) of the approved topics from the www.procon.org Website; insufficiently stated your position on the issue.
Partially selected one (1) of the approved topics from the www.procon.org Website; partially stated your position on the issue.
Satisfactorily selected one (1) of the approved topics from the www.procon.org Website; satisfactorily stated your position on the issue.
Thoroughly selected one (1) of the approved topics from the www.procon.org Website; thoroughly stated your position on the issue.
2. Identify three (3) premises under either the “Pro” or “Con” section from procon.org.
Weight: 30%
Did not submit or incompletely identified three (3) premises under either the “Pro” or “Con” section from procon.org.
Insufficiently identified three (3) premises under either the “Pro” or “Con” section from procon.org.
Partially identified three (3) premises under either the “Pro” or “Con” section from procon.org.
Satisfactorily identified three (3) premises under either the “Pro” or “Con” section under “Con” from procon.org.
Thoroughly identified three (3) premises under either the “Pro” or “Con” section “from procon.org.
3. Provide answers to the “believing questions” for the three (3) premises that disagree with your own position.
Weight: 40%
Did not submit or incompletely provided answers to the “believing questions” for the three (3) premises that disagree with your own position.
Insufficiently provided answers to the “believing questions” for the three (3) premises that disagree with your own position.
Partially provided answers to the “believing questions” for the three (3) premises that disagree with your own position.
Satisfactorily provided answers to the “believing questions” for the three (3) premises that disagree with your own position.
Thoroughly provided answers to the “believing questions” for the three (3) premises that disagree with your own position.
4. Use complete sentences and adhere to standard rules of English grammar, punctuation, mechanics, and spelling. Follow APA Style format.
Weight: 10%
Did not complete the assignment or had more than 9 errors in grammar, punctuation, mechanics, spelling.
Had 8-9 errors in grammar, punctuation, mechanics, spelling.
Had 6-7 different errors in grammar, punctuation, mechanics, spelling.
Had 4-5 different errors in grammar, punctuation, mechanics, spelling.
Had 0-3 different errors in grammar, punctuation, mechanics, spelling.
no reference except for the procon.org website on the specific page noted above
The Believing Game and How to Make Conflicting Opinions More Fruitful
Peter Elbow
[A chapter in Nurturing the Peacemakers in Our Students: A Guide to Teaching Peace, Empathy, and
Understanding. Chris Weber, editor. Heinemann, 2006. The present version contains a
few short
passages that had to be cut for space reasons in the published version.]
Don Quixote says he admires Sancho Panza because he
doubts everything and he believes everything.
In the chapter before this, Chris Weber suggests ways to help
students speak their minds, listen well, and engage in nonadversarial
dialogue rather than debate. His suggestions focus on outward behavior.
In this essay, I will move inward to the mysterious dimension of thinking
and feeling. I’ll start by asking you to imagine that you are looking at an
inkblot (for examples, ask Google Images for “inkblots”).
Imagine that you see something in it that interests and pleases you--
-but your colleagues or classmates don’t see what you see. In fact they
think you are crazy or disturbed for seeing it. What would you do if you
wanted to convince them that your interpretation makes sense?
If it were a matter of geometry, you could prove you are right (or
wrong!). But with inkblots, you don’t have logic’s leverage. Your only
hope is to get them to enter into your way of seeing---to have the
experience you are having. You need to get them to say the magic
words: “Oh now I see what you see.”
This means getting them to exercise the ability to see something
differently (i.e., seeing the same thing in multiple ways), and also the
willingness to risk doing so (not knowing where it will lead). In short, you
need them to be flexible both cognitively and emotionally. You can’t
make people enter into a new way of seeing, even if they are capable
of it. Perhaps your colleagues or classmates are bothered by what you
see in the inkblot. Perhaps they think it’s aberrant or psychotic. If you
want them to take the risk, your only option is to set a good example and
show that you are willing to see it the way they see it.
From Inkblots to Arguments
14
Interpreting inkblots is highly subjective, but the process serves to
highlight how arguments also have a subjective dimension. Few
arguments are settled by logic. Should we invade countries that might
attack us? Should we torture prisoners who might know what we need to
know? Should we drop a nuclear bomb on a country that did attack us?
And by the way, what grade is fair for this paper or this student? Should
we use grades at all?
I’m not denying the force of logic. Logic can uncover a genuine
error in someone’s argument. But logic cannot uncover an error in
someone’s position. If we could have proven that Iraq had no weapons
of mass destruction, that wouldn’t have proven that it was wrong to
invade Iraq. “We should invade Iraq” is a claim that is impossible to prove
or disprove. We can use logic to strengthen arguments for or against the
claim, but we cannot prove or disprove it. Over and over we see illogical
arguments for good ideas and logical arguments for bad ideas. We can
never prove that an opinion or position is wrong---or right. No wonder
people so seldom change their minds when someone finds bad
reasoning in their argument. (By the same token—or at least a very
similar token—it is impossible to prove or disprove the interpretation of a
text. For more on this, see my longer essays on the believing game.)
This explains a lot about how most people deal with differences of
opinion:
• Some people love to argue and disagree, and they do it for fun in a friendly way. They enjoy the disagreement and the give-and-take and
they let criticisms and even attacks roll right off their backs. It’s good
intellectual sport for them.
• Some people look like they enjoy the sport of argument. They stay friendly and rational---they’re “cool”---because they’ve been trained
well. “Don’t let your feelings cloud your thinking.” But inside they feel
hurt when others attack ideas they care about. They hunker down into
their ideas behind hidden walls.
• Some people actually get mad, raise their voices, dig in, stop listening, and even call each other names. Perhaps they realize that language
and logic have no power to make their listeners change their minds---
so they give in to shouting or anger.
• And some people---seeing that nothing can be proven with words--- just give up on argument. They retreat. “Let’s just not argue. You see it
15
your way, I’ll see it my way. That’s the end of it. There’s no use
talking.” They sidestep arguments and take a relativist position: any
opinion is as good as any other opinion. (It’s worth pondering why so
many students fall into this attitude.)
But sometimes people actually listen to each other, come to really see
the merit in opinions they started off fighting. Through listening to
someone else’s views, they do something amazing: they actually
change their thinking. Sometimes strong differences of opinion are
resolved---even heated arguments.
When this happens people demonstrate the two inkblot skills I just
described: the ability and the willingness to see something differently---or
in this case to think or understand something differently. (We often say “I
see” when we “understand” something differently). These are precious
skills, cognitive and psychological. We won’t have much luck
encouraging them in other people unless we develop them in ourselves.
With inkblots, the risk seems small. If we manage to see a blot the
way a classmate or colleague sees it, we don’t have to say, “Stupid me. I
was wrong.” It’s “live and let live” when we’re dealing with inkblots. With
arguments, however, it feels like win or lose. We often want people not
just to understand our position; we often want them to give up their
(“wrong, stupid”) position.
I used inkblots earlier to look for the subjective dimension in most
arguments (given that logic cannot prove or destroy a position). Now
inkblots can teach us something else. They can teach us that there’s
actually a “live-and-let-live” dimension in many arguments---probably
most. But we often feel arguments as win/lose situations because we so
naturally focus on how our side of an argument differs from the other
person’s side. We assume that one person has to say, “Stupid me. I was
wrong.”
The believing game will help us understand ideas we disagree with,
and thereby help us see that one one needs to lose or give up their
central idea. The believing game can help us see that both sides in an
argument are often right; or that both are right in a sense; or that both
positions are implicitly pointing to some larger, wiser position that both
arguers can agree on.
16
What is the Believing Game?
In a sense I’ve already explained it with my analogy between
inkblots and arguments. I can summarize it quickly now by contrasting it
with the doubting game.
The doubting game represents the kind of thinking most widely
honored and taught. It’s the disciplined practice of trying to be as
skeptical and analytic as possible with every idea we encounter. By
doubting well, we can discover hidden contradictions, bad reasoning, or
other weaknesses in ideas that look true or attractive. We scrutinize with
the tool of doubt. This is the tradition that Walter Lippman invokes:
The opposition is indispensable. A good statesman, like any other
sensible human being, always learns more from his opponents than
from his fervent supporters. For his supporters will push him to disaster
unless his opponents show him where the dangers are. So if he is
wise he will often pray to be delivered from his friends, because
they will ruin him. But, though it hurts, he ought . . . to pray never to
be left without opponents; for they keep him on the path of reason
and good sense.
The widespread veneration of “critical thinking” illustrates how our
intellectual culture venerates skepticism and doubting. (“Critical
thinking” is a fuzzy, fad term , but its various meanings usually appeal to
skepticism and analysis for the sake of uncovering bad thinking. When
people call a movement “critical linguistics” or “critical legal studies,”
they are saying that the old linguistics or legal studies are flawed by
being insufficiently skeptical or critical---too hospitable to something
that’s wrong.)
The believing game is the mirror image of the doubting game or
critical thinking. It’s the disciplined practice of trying to be as welcoming
as possible to every idea we encounter: not just listening to views
different from our own and holding back from arguing with them, but
actually trying to believe them. We can use the tool of believing to
scrutinize not for flaws but to find hidden virtues in ideas that are
unfashionable or repellent. Often we cannot see what’s good in
someone else’s idea (or in our own!) till we work at believing it. When an
idea goes against current assumptions and beliefs---or seems alien,
weird, dangerous---or if it’s poorly formulated---we often cannot see any
merit in it.
17
“Believing” is a Scary Word
Many people get nervous when I celebrate believing. They point to
an asymmetry between our sense of what “doubting” and “believing”
mean. Believing seems to entail commitment, where doubting does not.
It commonly feels as though we can doubt something without
committing ourselves to rejecting it---but that we cannot believe
something without committing ourselves to accepting it and even living
by it. Thus it feels as though we can doubt and remain unscathed, but
believing will scathe us. Indeed believing can feel hopelessly bound up
with religion. (“Do you BELIEVE? Yes, Lord, I BELIEVE!”)
This contrast in meanings is a fairly valid picture of natural ,individual
acts of doubting and believing. (Though I wonder if doubting leaves us
fully unchanged.) But it’s not a picture of doubting and believing as
methodological disciplines or unnatural games. Let me explain the
distinction.
Natural individual acts of doubting happen when someone tells us
something that seems dubious or hard to believe. (“You say the earth is
spinning? I doubt it. I feel it steady under my feet.”) But our culture has
learned to go way beyond natural individual acts of doubting. We
humans had to struggle for a long time to learn how to doubt unnaturally
as a methodological discipline. We now know that for good thinking, we
must doubt everything, not just what’s dubious; indeed the whole point
of critical thinking is to try to doubt what we find most obvious or true or
right (as Lippman advises).
In order to develop systematic doubting, we had to overcome
believing: the natural pull to believe what's easy to believe, what we
want to believe, or what powerful people tell us to believe. (It’s easy to
believe that the earth is stationary.) As a culture, we learned systematic
doubting through the growth of philosophical thinking (Greek thinkers
developing logic, Renaissance thinkers developing science, and
Enlightenment thinkers pulling away from established religion). And we
each had to learn to be skeptical as individuals, too---for example
learning not to believe that if we are very very good, Santa Claus/God
will bring us everything we want. As children, we begin to notice that
naïve belief leads us astray. As adults we begin to notice the dreadful
18
things that belief leads humans to do---like torturing alleged
witches/prisoners till they "confess."
Now that we’ve finally learned systematic doubting with its tools of
logic and strict reasoning and its attitude of systematic skepticism---
critical thinking---we are likely to end up afraid of believing itself. We had
to learn to distrust natural believing (“My parents/country/God will take
care of me whenever I am in need.”). So believing can seem a scary
word because our culture has not yet learned to go beyond natural acts
of naïve believing to develop unnatural believing as a methodological
discipline. In short, the believing game is not much honored or even
known (though it’s not new).
The methodology of the doubting game gives us a model for the
methodology of the believing game. When the doubting game asks us
to doubt an idea, it doesn't ask us to throw it away forever. We couldn’t
do that because the game teaches us to doubt all ideas, and we’ll learn
to find weaknesses even in good ideas. We can’t throw all ideas away.
The scrutiny of doubt is methodological, provisional, conditional. So when
a good doubter finally decides what to believe or do, this involves an
additional act of judgment and commitment. The doubting game gives
good evidence, but it doesn’t do our judging and committing for us.
Similarly, when the believing game asks us to believe all ideas---
especially those that seem most wrong---it cannot ask us to marry them
or commit ourselves to them. Our believing is also methodological,
conditional, provisional---unnatural. (It’s hard to try to believe conflicting
ideas all at once, but we can try to enter into them one after another.)
And so too, if we commit ourselves to accepting an idea because the
believing game helped us see virtues in it, this involves an additional act
of judgment and commitment. The believing game gives us good
evidence, but it doesn’t do our deciding for us.
In short, we must indeed continue to resist the pull to believe what's
easy to believe. But believing what’s easy to believe is far different from
using the disciplined effort to believe as an intellectual methodological
tool in order to find hidden strengths in ideas that people want to ignore.
A Surprising Blind Spot for the Doubting Game
19
The doubting and believing games have symmetrical weaknesses:
the doubting game is poor at helping us find hidden virtues; the believing
game is poor at helping us find hidden flaws. But many people don’t
realize that the doubting game is also poor at reaching one of its main
goals: helping us find hidden flaws in our own thinking.
The flaws in our own thinking usually come from our assumptions---our
ways of thinking that we accept without noticing. But it’s hard to doubt
what we can’t see because we unconsciously take it for granted. The
believing game comes to the rescue here. Our best hope for finding
invisible flaws in what we can’t see in our own thinking is to enter into
different ideas or points of view---ideas that carry different assumptions.
Only after we’ve managed to inhabit a different way of thinking will our
currently invisible assumptions become visible to us.
This blind spot in the doubting game shows up frequently in
classrooms and other meetings. When smart people are trained only in
critical thinking, they get better and better at doubting and criticizing
other people’s ideas. They use this skill particularly well when they feel a
threat to their own ideas or their unexamined assumptions. Yet they feel
justified in fending-off what they disagree with because they feel that this
doubting activity is “critical thinking.” They take refuge in the feeling that
they would be “unintellectual” if they said to an opponent what in fact
they ought to say: “Wow, your idea sounds really wrong to me. It must
be alien to how I think. Let me try to enter into it and see if there’s
something important that I’m missing. Let me see if I can get a better
perspective on my own thinking.” In short, if we want to be good at
finding flaws in our own thinking (a goal that doubters constantly
trumpet), we need the believing game.
The Believing Game is Not Actually New
If we look closely at the behavior of genuinely smart and productive
people, we will see that many of them have exactly this skill of entering
into views that conflict with their own. John Stuart Mill is a philosopher
associated with the doubting game, but he also advises good thinkers to
engage in the central act of the believing game:
[People who] have never thrown themselves into the mental
position of those who think differently from them . . . do not, in any
20
proper sense of the word, know the doctrine which they themselves
profess. (129)
Yet this skill of sophisticated unnatural belief is not much understood or
celebrated in our culture---and almost never taught.
Imagine, for example, a seminar or a meeting where lots of ideas
come up. One person is quick to point out flaws in each idea as it is
presented. A second person mostly listens and gets intrigued with each
idea--and tends to make comments like these: “Oh I see” and “That’s
interesting” and “Tell me more about such and such” and “As I go with
your thinking, I begin to see some things I never noticed before.” This
second person may be appreciated as a good listener, but the first
person will tend to be considered smarter and a better thinker because
of that quick skill at finding flaws.
I used to feel that I was unintelligent because when one person
gave an argument I would feel, “Oh that’s a good idea,” but then when
the other person argued the other way, I found myself feeling, “Oh that
sounds good, too.” I wondered what was the matter with my loose,
sloppy mind to let me agree with people and ideas that are completely
at odds with each other. The “smart people” tended to argue cleverly
and find flaws that I didn’t notice. But now I’m finally insisting that my
instinctive ability to play the believing game is not just “niceness” or
sloppy thinking; it’s a crucial intellectual strength rather than a weakness-
--a discipline that needs to be taught and developed.
Let me emphasize that I’m not arguing against the doubting game.
We need the ability to be skeptical and find flaws. Indeed, the doubting
game probably deserves the last word in any valid process of trying to
work out trustworthy thinking. For even though the scrutiny of belief may
lead us to choose a good idea that most people at first wanted to throw
away, nevertheless, we mustn’t commit ourselves to that idea before
applying the scrutiny of doubt to check for hidden problems.
My only argument is against the monopoly of the doubting game as
the only kind of good thinking. We need both disciplines. Some of our
most needed insights come from opinions that are easy to criticize or
dismiss. But those insights are only available if people work at entering
into such opinions in search of unnoticed virtues.
21
Concrete Ways to Learn to Play the Believing Game
As teachers and students we are in a good position to learn the
ability to see things differently from how we usually see them, and the
willingness to risk doing it. If we want to learn those skills, it helps to notice
the inner stances ---the cognitive and psychological dispositions---we
need for doubting and believing:
• If we want to doubt or find flaws in ideas that we are tempted to accept or believe (perhaps they are ideas that “everyone knows are
true”), we need to work at extricating or distancing ourselves from
those ideas. There’s a kind of language that helps here: clear,
impersonal sentences that lay bare the logic or lack of logic in them.
• If, on the other hand, we want to believe ideas that we are tempted to reject (“Anyone can see that’s a crazy idea”)---if we are trying to
enter in or experience or dwell in those ideas---we benefit from the
language of imagination, narrative, and the personal experience.
Here are some specific practices to help us experience things from
someone else’s point of view.
1. If people are stuck in a disagreement, we can invoke Carl Rogers’
application of “active listening.” John must not try to argue his point till
he has restated Mary’s point to her satisfaction.
2. But what if John has trouble seeing things from Mary’s point of view?
His lame efforts to restate her view show that “he doesn't get it.” He
probably needs to stop talking and listen; keep his mouth shut. Thus, in a
discussion where someone is trying to advance a view and everyone
fights it, there is a simple rule of thumb: the doubters need to stop talking
and simply give extended floor time to the minority view. The following
three concrete activities give enormous help here:
• The three-minute or five-minute rule. Any participant who feels he or she is not being heard can make a sign and invoke the rule: no one
else can talk for three or five minutes. This voice speaks, we listen; we
cannot reply.
• Allies only---no objections. Others can speak---but only those who are having more success believing or entering into or assenting to the
minority view. No objections allowed. (Most people are familiar with
this “no-objections” rule from brainstorming.)
22
• “Testimony session.” Participants having a hard time being heard or understood are invited to tell stories of the experiences that led them
to their point of view and to describe what it's like having or living with
this view. Not only must the rest of us not answer or argue or disagree
while they are speaking; we must refrain, even afterwards, from
questioning their stories or experiences or feelings. We may speak only
to their ideas. (This process is particularly useful when issues of race,
gender, and sexual orientation are being discussed.)
The goal here is safety. Most speakers feel unsafe if they sense we
are just waiting to jump in with all our objections. But we listeners need
safety, too. We are trying to enter into a view we want to quarrel with or
feel threatened by. We’re trying to learn the difficult skill of in-dwelling. It's
safer for us if we have permission simply not to talk about it any more for
a while. We need time for the words we resist just to sink in for a while with
no comment.
3. The language of story and poetry helps us experience alien ideas.
Stories, metaphors, and images can often find a path around our
resistance. When it’s hard to enter into a new point of view, try telling a
story of someone who believes it; imagine and describe someone who
sees things this way; tell the story of events that might have led people to
have this view of the world; what would it be like to be someone who
sees things this way? Write a story or poem about the world that this view
implies.
4. Step out of language. Language itself can sometimes get in the way
of trying to experience or enter into a point of view different from our
own. There are various productive ways to set language aside. We can
draw or sketch images (rough stick figures are fine). What do you
actually see when you take this position? It’s also powerful to use
movement, gesture, dance, sounds, and role-playing.
5. Silence. For centuries, people have made good use of silence for in-
dwelling. If we’re having trouble trying to believe someone’s idea,
sometimes it’s helpful for no one to say anything for a couple of minutes.
That’s not much time out of a meeting or conference or class hour, but it
can be surprisingly fertile.
6. Private writing. There's a kind of silence involved when everyone
engages in private writing. Stop talking and do 7-10 minutes of writing for
23
no one else’s eyes. What's crucial is the invitation to language in
conditions of privacy and safety.
7. Use the physical voice. When it’s hard to enter into a piece of writing
that feels difficult or distant, for example something written by someone
very different from us---or an intricate work like a Shakespeare sonnet---it
helps to try to read it aloud as well and meaningfully as possible. (When
I’m teaching a longer text, I choose crux passages of a few paragraphs
or a page.) The goal is not good acting; the goal is simply to say the
words so that we feel every meaning in them---so that we fully mean
every meaning. Get the words to “sound right” or to carry the meanings
across—for example, to listeners who don’t have a text. After we have
three or four different readings of the same passage, we can discuss
which ones manage to “sound right”---and usually these readings help us
enter in or assent. (It’s not fair to put students on the spot by asking them
to read with no preparation time. I ask students to prepare these reading
at home or practice them briefly in class in pairs.)
This activity illustrates something interesting about language. It’s
impossible simply to say words so they “sound right" without dwelling in
them and thus feeling their meaning. So instead of asking students to
“study carefully” this Shakespeare sonnet, I say, “Practice reading it
aloud till you can say every word with meaning.” This involves giving a
kind of bodily assent.
8. Nonadversarial argument. Finally, the classroom is an ideal place to
practice nonadversarial forms of argument. Our traditional model of
argument is a zero-sum game: “If I'm right, you must be wrong.” Essays
and dissertations traditionally start off by trying to demolish the views of
opponents. “Unless I criticize every other idea,” the assumption goes, “I
won’t have a clear space for my idea.” But this approach is usually
counterproductive--except with readers who already agree with you
and don’t need to be persuaded. This traditional argument structure
says to readers: “You cannot agree with my ideas---or even hear them---
until after you admit that you’ve been wrong or stupid.”
The structure of nonadversarial argument is simple, but it takes
practice and discipline: argue only for your position, not against other
positions. This is easy for me here since I have no criticisms at all of the
doubting game or critical thinking in itself. It’s much harder if I really hate
the idea I’m fighting. It’s particularly hard if my essential argument is
negative: “Don’t invade Iraq.” So yes, there are some situations in which
24
we cannot avoid arguing why an idea is wrong. Yet even in my position
on Iraq, there is, in fact, some space for nonadversarial argument. I can
talk about the advantages of not invading Iraq---and not try to refute for
invasion. In this way, I would increase the chances of my opponent
actually hearing my arguments.
The general principle is this: If all I have to offer are negative reasons
why the other person’s idea is bad, I’ll probably make less progress than if
I can give some positive reasons for my alternative idea---and even
acknowledge why the other person might favor her idea. (For more on
nonadversarial argument, see my “Introduction” xviii-xxiii.)
I can end by glancing back at the inkblots. Arguments that look
conflicting might both be somehow valid or right. They might need to be
articulated better or seen from a larger view---a view the disputants
haven't yet figured out. I may be convinced that someone else’s idea is
dead wrong, but if I’m willing to play the believing game with it, I will not
only set a good example, I may even be able to see how we are both
on the right track. Nonadversarial argument and the believing game
help us work out larger frames of reference and better ideas.
Works Cited
Elbow, Peter. “Appendix Essay. The Doubting Game and the Believing
Game: An Analysis of the Intellectual Process.” In Writing Without
Teachers. Oxford University Press, 1973. 147-91.
---. “Bringing the Rhetoric of Assent and The Believing Game Together--
and into the Classroom.” College English 67.4 (March 2005): 388-99.
---. Introduction. Everyone Can Write: Essays Toward a Hopeful Theory of
Writing and Teaching Writing. NY: Oxford University Press, 2000.
---. “Methodological Doubting and Believing: Contraries in Inquiry.” In
Embracing Contraries: Explorations in Learning and Teaching.
Oxford University Press, 1986. 254-300.
Graff, Gerald. Clueless in Academe: How Schooling Obscures the Life of
the Mind. New Haven: Yale UP, 2003.
Lippman, Walter. “The Indispensable Opposition.” Atlantic Monthly
(August 1939). It’s notable that this essay is canonized in many
editions of The Norton Reader (e.g., in the 6th edition, pages 850-55).
Mill, John Stuart. On Liberty. London, Dent, 1951.
25
Rogers, Carl. "Communication: Its Blocking and Its Facilitation." On
Becoming a Person. NY: Houghton Mifflin, 1961.
Tannen, Deborah. The Argument Culture: Moving From Debate to
Dialogue. Random House, 1998