Reading Analysis Writing
Practice: Architecture, Technique + Representation is a book of essays by architect Stan Allen. Conversant in contemporary
theory and architectural history, Allen writes from his perspective as a working architect, rather than that of a critic
or historian. Architecture has always been a synthetic discipline, constantly importing ideas from other fi elds; but
those concepts, as they enter architecture’s fi eld of operations, are transformed by the specifi city of the architect’s
expertise. The book examines this tension between architecture’s defi nition of itself as an autonomous discipline, and an
always changing landscape of ideas and technologies. This new edition includes revised essays together with previously
unpublished work. Allen’s seminal piece on Field Conditions is included in this reworked, revised and redesigned volume.
Stan Allen is a practicing architect and Dean of the School of Architecture, Princeton University. Responding to the
complexity of the modern city in creative ways, Stan Allen has developed an extensive catalogue of urbanistic strate-
gies, in particular looking at fi eld theory, landscape architecture and ecology as models to revitalize the practices of
urban design. In addition to design awards and competition prizes, he has been awarded Fellowships in Architecture
from the New York Foundation for the Arts, The New York State Council on the Arts, a Design Arts Grant from the
National Endowment for the Arts, a Graham Foundation Grant, and a President’s Citation from The Cooper Union.
PRACTICE: ARCHITECTURE
TECHNIQUE + REPRESENTATION
EX PA
N D
ED S
EC O
N D
E D
IT IO
N
STAN ALLEN
PRACTICE: ARCHITECTURE
TECHNIQUE + REPRESENTATION
EX PA
N D
ED S
EC O
N D
E D
IT IO
N
AFTERWORD BY JEFFREY KIPNIS
Acknowledgements
INTRODUCTION Practice vs. Project
DRAWINGS
Constructing with Lines: On Projection Postscript: Review of Robin Evans: The Projective Cast
Notations and Diagrams: Mapping the Intangible
Terminal Velocities: The Compu ter in the Design Studio Postscript: The Digital Complex
BUILDINGS
Mies’ Theater of E� ects: The New National Gallery, Berlin
The Guggenheim Refi gured: The Solomon R. Guggenheim Museum
Le Corbusier and Modernist Movement: The Carpenter Center for Visual Arts
CITIES
Urbanisms in the Plural
The Thick 2-D: Mat-Building in the Contemporary City
From Object to Field: Field Conditions in Architecture and Urbanism
AFTERWORD by Je� rey Kipnis Some Side E� ects of a Friend's Excellent Book
Image Credits Index
VI
X
2
40
70
96
116
134
158
192
216
244
250
252
I
II
III
IV
V
VI
VII
VIII
IX
IX
light chimineys + el 670.00
roof high pt. + el 663.00
meeting rooms + el 656.50
auditorium foyer + el 649.50
Stan Allen Section Projection, Extension of the Museo del Prado, 1998
Gio Ponti Eleven Meter Structural Test Model, Pirelli Tower, Milan, 1956
XI
INTRODUCTION: Practice vs. Project
CONTINGENCIESAlmost unique among creative practices, architecture’s objective is given from outside. Architects, unlike painters, sculptors, or poets, depend on clients and pa-
trons to execute their work. As a consequence, they are likely to work across a wide array of
scales, building types, climates, economics, and building cultures. Architecture is of necessity
a discipline of circumstance and situation. Even in the most ideal careers, many decisions are
beyond the control of the individual architect. The process of design and construction is char-
acterized by constant tactical adjustments made to the demands of clients, codes, consultants,
budgets, builders, and regulatory agencies, not to mention the complex logistics of construction
itself. Moreover, architects today practice far from home, and each new site presents unfamiliar
conditions. As creative subjects, architects react to these demands, inventing in response to the
occasion of the commission, specifying and particularizing a given set of abstract variables. The
practice of architecture tends to be messy and inconsistent precisely because it has to negotiate
a reality that is itself messy and inconsistent.
I must say that what interests me more is to focus on what the Greeks called techne, that is to say, a practical rationality governed by a conscious goal … if one wanted to do a history of architecture, I think that it should be much more along the lines of that general history of the techne, rather than the histories of either the exact sciences or the inexact ones.
Michel Foucault
Art and architecture are practices, not sciences. The constructions of science aspire to univer- sal application. Pictures and buildings need only work where they are.
Dave Hickey
XII
Against this landscape of contingency, architectural theory has traditionally served a unifying
function. Without a larger ideological framework, it is argued, the architect runs the risk of reacting
passively to the multiple and often contradictory demands of context, clients, regulating agencies,
media, or economics. Architecture, it is argued, needs a grand narrative in order not to be entirely
consumed by these small narratives of opportunity and constraint. And so, in order to legitimate its
mechanical procedures, practice appeals to a project: an overarching theoretical construct, defi ned
from someplace other than the studio or the building site, and expressed in a medium other than
buildings and drawings. Detached from the operational sites of technique, theory stakes a claim on a
world of concepts uncontaminated by real world contingencies. Theory needs distance for its refl ec-
tions; but as a consequence of that detachment, the possibility of incremental change from within is
held in check. Theory’s promise is to make up for what practice lacks: to confer unity on the wildly
disparate procedures of design and construction.
This tension is only partially o� set by the tendency of conventional practice to repeat known
solutions. Too often, contemporary practice oscillates between mechanical repetition and shallow
novelty. Conventional practice renounces theory, but in so doing, it simply reiterates unstated the-
oretical assumptions. It works according to a series of enabling codes, which themselves comprise
a random sampling of the dictates of professional practice and the learned habits of normal design
culture. It is these unexamined codes that give practice a bad name. The protocols of normal practice
may be modifi ed or adapted in response to circumstance, but are rarely challenged. Design is reduced
to the implementation of rules set down elsewhere. If theory imposes regulated ideological criteria
over the undisciplined heterogeneity of the real, the unstated assumptions of conventional practice
enforce known solutions and safe repetitions. In both cases, small di� erences accumulate, but they
never add up to make a di� erence.
If conventional practice and theoretically driven critical practices are similarly structured, it
cannot be a question of going beyond theory, or of leaving theory behind. What is proposed
here is instead a notion of practice flexible enough to engage the complexity of the real, yet
sufficiently secure in its own technical and theoretical bases to go beyond the simple reflec-
tion of the real as given. Not a static reflection of concepts defined elsewhere (either the codes
of professional practice or the dictates of ideologically driven theory) but a rigorous forward
movement, capable of producing new concepts out of the hard logic of architecture’s working
procedures. Paradoxically, practice, which is usually assumed to be unproblematically identi-
fied with reality, will discover new uses for theory only as it moves closer to the complex and
problematic character of the real itself. Practice necessarily respects the verifiable laws that
govern matter and forces, but it is also attentive to the fact that these laws operate without
regard to consistency or established conventions of rational expression. This attention to the
gaps and inconsistencies in theory’s fit to reality is, as T. S. Kuhn has pointed out, a tremendous
source of invention and creativity.1 It is precisely when practice and experimentation turn up
inconsistencies in the “normal science” that new theories are produced.
XIII
Hence it is of little use to see theory and practice as competing abstractions, and to argue for one
over the other. Theories and practices are both produced in defi nable spaces, by active, conscious
subjects. Intelligent, creative practices — the writing of theory included — are always more than the
habitual exercise of rules defi ned elsewhere. Practice is not a static construct, but is defi ned precise-
ly by its movements and trajectories. There is no theory, there is no practice. There are only practices,
which consist in action and agency. They unfold in time, and their repetitions are never identical. It
is for this reason that the know-how of practice (whether of writing or design) is a continual source
of innovation and change. Tactical improvisations accumulate over time to produce new models for
operation. But these new patterns of operation produced in practice are always provisional. Inas-
much as they derive from experience and data, they are always open to revision on the basis of new
experiences, or new data. Deliberately executed, architecture’s procedures are capable of producing
systematic thought: serial, precise, and clinical; something that resembles theory but will always be
marked by the constructive/creative criteria of practice.
Pragmatism unsti� ens all our theories; it limbers them up and sets each one at work.
William James
MATERIAL PRACTICES: AN ‘EROTICS OF DOUBT’
I nstead of opposing theory and practice, imagine competing categories of practice: one primarily textual, bound up with representation and interpretation: a hermeneutic, or discursive practice; and the other concerned with matter, forces, and material change: a material practice. The consequence of this would be to say that there is no fixed category called
“practice,” no fixed category called “theory.” There are only practices: practices of writing, which
are primarily critical, discursive, or interpretive, and material practices: activities that trans-
form reality by producing new objects or new organizations of matter.
Discursive practices work in the space between texts, and they produce more texts. Material practices
often involve operations of translation, transposition or trans-coding of multiple media. Although they
work to transform matter, material practices necessarily work through the intermediary of abstract
codes such as projection, notation or calculation. Constantly mixing media in this way, material prac-
tices produce new concepts out of the materials and procedures of work itself. The vector of analysis in
hermeneutic practices always points toward the past, whereas material practices analyze the present in
order to project transformations into the future. Discursive practices look critically at what already ex-
ists (“things made”), while material practices bring new things into being: “things in the making.” 2
XIV
Architecture, I want to say right from the beginning, is a material, and not a discursive practice, and
by being clear about what this means, we can steer around much of the obscurity that character-
izes debates today. If you understand architecture as “built discourse” it becomes very easy to forget
about the specifi city of building and begin to compare architecture to other discursive practices such
as writing, fi lm, new media, or graphic design. And if you do so, you begin to notice that, compared
to these other practices, architecture is relatively inert as discourse. It cannot approach the transpar-
ency and speed of these other media. And so, if discursive communication (commentary, critique or
explanation) is your ultimate criterion, there is a great temptation to leave architecture behind, and
to move toward these other practices. It you try to make architecture do something that it does not
fundamentally do very well, you may decide in the end that it’s not worth the trouble. (And practic-
ing architecture is, if nothing else, a troublesome pursuit.) In contrast to this attitude, which sees
architecture’s materiality as an impediment to be overcome — something that is slowing it down in
a world of speed and communication — I have consistently tried to look more openly at the specifi c
opportunities presented by architecture’s material and instrumental properties. Visual culture and
material practices have their own rules, and those rules are di� erent from those that govern texts.
It is for this reason that architecture has never been particularly e� ective as a vehicle of criticism. It is,
on the contrary, insistently a rmative and instrumental. Material practices do not comment on the
world, they operate in and on the world. They produce ideas and e� ects through the volatile medium
of artifacts, short-circuiting the established pathways of theory and discourse. This is architecture’s
attraction: its source of creativity, operational power, and — not the least — pleasure. Today, the most
interesting practitioners no longer ask what architecture is, or what it means, but rather what it can
do. From a theoretical point of view, it is less a matter of arguing in favor of architecture’s instrumen-
tality as it is acknowledging that any theoretical approach that cannot account for architecture’s in-
trinsically instrumental character is going to fall short.
One of the urgent consequences of this more pragmatic approach would be to move us away
from the private world of the architect’s design process, and its preoccupation with questions of
meaning, and the politics of identity, to an open discussion of architecture’s agency in the public
sphere. It would necessarily shift attention away from the architect as the producer of mean-
ing, and pay closer attention instead to the life of buildings in the world. It might help to get
us beyond the fiction that meaning is the result of something that happens in the course of the
design process. Meaning is not something added to architecture; it is a much larger, and a slip-
perier, momentary thing. It is not located in the architecture: it is what happens to and around
architecture as part of a complex social exchange. It happens in the interval, as the result of an
encounter between architecture and its public, in the field.
A material practice, therefore, would have little to do with the easy acquiescence to existing norms and
conventions of agency and instrumentality. It would be instead persistently skeptical and contrary, a
stubborn practice that would hold those generic norms to strict performative criteria, and leave them
Tom Caruso
Disagree
Tom Caruso
Disagree
XV
behind when they fall short. When the only certainty is change itself, practice can no longer depend on
stable rules and conventions. Tethered to a fast-moving reality, material practices need to be agile and
responsive, which often requires that they leave behind some of the weighty baggage of received ideas.
This is a more uncertain, but also more optimistic program. Conceived as a material practice, archi-
tecture achieves a practical (and therefore provisional) unity inferred on the basis of its ensemble of
procedures, rather than a theoretical unity conferred from without by ideology or discourse. Such a
notion of practice maintains a deep respect for history, and for architecture’s past. The accumulated
catalog of architecture’s rules and procedures is accepted as a starting point, a common language
that serves as a basis for any conversation. And yet, unlike the conservative project that would see the
structure of the discipline as a limit, historically defi ned, the pragmatic know-how of technique does
not necessarily respect precedent.3 The criterion of productivity simply bypasses outmoded working
strategies, leaving the discipline open to new techniques, which may in turn be incorporated into the
catalog of architecture’s working procedures.
Material practices unfold in time, with a full awareness of the history of the discipline, but never satis-
fi ed to simply repeat, or to execute a system of rules defi ned elsewhere. Architecture’s limits are un-
derstood pragmatically — as a resource and an opportunity — and not a defi ning boundary. The prac-
titioner looks for performative multiplicities in the interplay between an open catalog of procedures
and a stubbornly indi� erent reality. Constraint is not an obstacle to creativity, but an opportunity for
invention, provoking the discovery of new techniques. Under the pragmatics of material practice, the
fi xed structure of the discipline is neither rejected nor a rmed. A hardheaded skepticism is applied as
much to the dictates of theory as to the inherited conventions of normal practice. They are subject
not to critical interrogation, but to an “erotics” of doubt:
The space of doubt di� ers from the space of certainty in that doubt narrows the
distance between theory and the world. If theoretical refl ection entails being at
a certain remove from the world, doubt returns thought to openness before the
world; it involves a loss of mastery and control which places thought in a more
vulnerable relation to the world than before.4
Material practices are tools to open architecture to the world; refusing the safety of theory’s disem-
bodied distance, a material practice is marked by the uncertainty of an ever-shifting reference in the
world itself. Not a Cartesian doubt that works by process of elimination to arrive at a core of unshak-
able propositions, but a tactic for dealing with an imperfect reality with a catalog of tools that is itself
always incomplete, imperfect, and inadequate.
Tom Caruso
agree
XVI
There can be no di� erence which doesn’t make a di� erence — no di� erence in abstract truth which does not express itself in a di� erence of concrete fact, and of conduct consequent upon the fact, imposed on somebody, somehow, somewhere, and somewhen. William James
TECHNIQUES: DIFFERENCES THAT MAKE A DIFFERENCE
W hen speaking of techniques of construction, it is important to remember that the archi-tect is not a builder, but a specifi er of construction technique. The architect works with a knowledge of the methods and materials of construction in both design and implementa- tion, but the impact of this knowledge is indirect. What is more signifi cant is the way in which the vari-
ables of construction are factored into the calculus of architecture’s procedures. This leads away from
a theory of “truth to materials” toward an examination of consequences and experiential e� ects. The
claim, for example, that Le Corbusier, in the Carpenter Center (Chapter 6) is able to achieve a sense of
mobility and lightness with a material that is not in itself intrinsically lightweight turns on a detailed dis-
cussion of some of the technical aspects of the building’s reinforced concrete construction. Innovation
and technical constraint are shown to be closely bound up with formal expression.
The design history of the Guggenheim Museum is signifi cant in this regard, and was crucial for me
in defi ning the notion of practice outlined here. In 1991, I wrote that Frank Lloyd Wright could “de-
ploy multiple structural principles with e� ective operational freedom precisely because he was com-
mitted to structural rationality as practice, not as project” (Chapter 5). What I meant was something
like this: early models showed the spiral ramp of the museum propped up on thin columns, a solu-
tion clearly at odds with the organic continuity Wright desired. In time, Wright devised an integrat-
ed structural solution that did not distinguish between supporting structure and enclosing enve-
lope. While architecturally compelling, this solution proved impractical from a constructional point
of view. Wright in the end accepted a solution that, while literally inconsistent with the conceptual
unity originally proposed, was itself logical and e cient. What is revealing, and speaks as much to
Wright’s tactical fl exibility as to his intimate knowledge of building technique, is that, while literally
segmented, the experience of the building is still one of integrated structure and smooth fl ow. In
practice, the desired continuity is in no way compromised by the apparent structural expedient.
The di� erence between practice and project is therefore marked by the pragmatic idea of “di� erences
that make a di� erence.” It appeals to concrete di� erences of performance and behavior and not to
abstract relations between ideas and discourses. For Wright, as for most of the architects that inter-
est me, buildings are always more than individual components of a larger project. They are not ex-
XVII
amples of principles enunciated elsewhere, or cases to be tested against the rule of theory’s law. Par-
ticular instances are met with particular solutions. Consistency and rationality are guaranteed by
the hard logic of structure, and by the indi� erent behavior of materials themselves. In the case of
Wright, the rational behavior of structure is not an absolute fact to be given material expression, but
an opportunity and a resource — a point of provisional stability to be freely handled.5 The measure of
Wright’s “mastery” of the terms of building is as much his knowledge of where and when to compro-
mise, as in any mythic appeal to integrity and the “truth to materials.” This is a way of working that
assumes that the ability of architecture to generate perceivable experiences and sensations in the
world — practical consequences and e� ects — is more important than its conformance or non-con-
formance with some abstract set of theoretical criteria.
To claim that architecture is a material practice, working in and among the world of things — an instru-
mental practice capable of transforming reality — is not to lose sight of architecture’s complicated com-
promise with techniques of representation.6 Inasmuch as architects work at a distance from the material
reality of their discipline, they necessarily work through the mediation of systems of representation. Ar-
chitecture itself is marked by this promiscuous mixture of the real and the abstract: at once a collection of
activities characterized by a high degree of abstraction, and at the same time directed toward the produc-
tion of materials and artifacts that are undeniably real. The techniques of representation are never neu-
tral, and architecture’s abstract means of imagining and realizing form leave their traces on the work. To
understand representation as technique (in Foucault’s broader sense of techne) is therefore to pay atten-
tion to the paradoxical character of a discipline that operates to organize and transform material reality,
but must do so at a distance, and through highly abstract means. To concentrate on the instrumental-
ity of drawing is to pay attention to the complex process of what Robin Evans has called “translations”
between drawing and building. It is this e� ort to understand the tra c between geometry, imagina-
tion and construction that has motivated the three essays on drawing techniques that open this volume.
The characterization of architecture as a material practice deserves one fi nal qualifi cation. These
translations between drawing and building today take place within a larger fl ow of images and
information. Architecture’s culture of instrumental representations cannot help but be a� ected by its
intersection with this dominant media culture. Architecture has always maintained a mechanism of
explanation and normative description alongside material production: treatises, catalogs, journals,
conferences, and texts. In the past this was related to pedagogy, and the dissemination of profes-
sional information. Today there is an accelerated, spiraling motion whereby materials from outside
architecture (most notably, the immaterial e� ects of fi lm, new media, or graphic design), have been
cycled back through the discipline to enlarge architecture’s catalog of available techniques.
This image culture belongs to the new ways of thinking and seeing that have emerged with
modernity: shifting mental schemas that mark our uncertain position in the modern world, and force
us to see how the practice of architecture has been constantly revised by the complex currents of
twentieth century thought.7 Michael Speaks has proposed that the exercise of what he calls design intel-
XVIII
ligence, enables architects to navigate more e� ectively in this new, information-dense context.8 Speaks’
suggestive formulation plays on two meanings of the word “intelligence.” On the one hand, it recognizes
that architects and other design professionals possess a specifi c form of expertise, a synthetic and pro-
jective capacity unique to their own discipline. Design intelligence in this sense implies the thoughtful
application of that expertise to problems specifi c to architecture. On the other hand, just as military in-
telligence is necessarily composed of rumors and fragmented information, from often suspect sources (a
high noise to signal ratio) it implies that architects need to be open to the “chatter” of the world outside of
their own fi eld, and alert to new ways of interpreting, and putting that information to work. As in intelli-
gence work, with immense quantities of information now simultaneously available, it is no longer access
to information that counts, but the ability to process, organize, and visualize information that is crucial.
And so, if I maintain a provisional distinction between the instrumental consequences of representa-
tion within the discipline of architecture, and architecture’s complex interplay with social and cultural
representations, it is not to ignore the moments of intersection and overlap. Material practices must be
robust, information-dense, and open to change and revision. Its practitioners realize that the new real-
ity of technology and the city is one of continual obsolescence, and that the only way to survive change is
to change. Moreover, material practices trust in the intelligence of architecture’s audience, understand-
ing that architecture has many publics, and that the signifi cant work of architecture is one that allows
continual revision and rereading, teasing out new meanings as the context changes. This necessitates a
close attention to the material e� ects and worldly consequences of all of architecture’s matter — seman-
tic and material — while maintaining a strict indi� erence as to the origin of those e� ects.
And indeed, it is easier to walk with music than without it. Of course, it is just as easy to walk while talking up a storm, when the act of walking disappears from our consciousness.
Viktor Shklovsky
TRAJECTORIES
M ichel de Certeau employs the fi gure of the walker in the city to describe the errant trajec-tories of everyday practices among the systematic space of the proper. For de Certeau, “the geometrical space of urbanists and architects seems to have the status of a ‘proper meaning’ constructed by the grammarians and linguists in order to have a normal and normative level
to which they can compare the drifting of ‘fi gurative’ language.” Within his schema, the wandering
course of the pedestrian is compared to the enunciative function in language: “The act of walking is
XIX
to the urban system what the speech act is to language or to statements uttered.” 9 This free move-
ment that de Certeau describes (“a Brownian variability of directions” in Deleuze and Guattari10) is
guaranteed by the tactical improvisations of multiple individuals. De Certeau understood that there
can never be a perfect correspondence between the regulated geometrical structure of the planned
city and the unruly practices it supports. The city’s inhabitants are always ready to take advantage of
this mismatch between structure and performance. This in turn suggests that the control exercised
by any disciplinary regime can never be total. Resistance will fi nd other pathways around, or under,
or through, the constraints imposed from outside, pathways that lead away from transgression, cata-
strophic overthrow, withdrawal or retreat.11
De Certeau describes a series of “tricky and stubborn procedures that elude discipline without being
outside the fi eld in which it is exercised.” 12 He has confi dence that there will always exist fi ssures and
cracks that provide openings for tactical reworkings. Making opportunistic use of these footholds,
the creativity of everyday practices can often outwit the rigid structures of imposed order, and outma-
neuver the weighty apparatus of institutional control: “The long poem of walking manipulates spatial
organizations, no matter how panoptic they may be: it is neither foreign to them (it can only take
place within them) nor in conformity with them (it does not receive its identity from them). It creates
shadows and ambiguities within them.” 13
What is not immediately obvious in de Certeau’s writings is a subtext that would associate the
geometrical space of the planned city with the systematic constructs of theory. A concept of theory
as regulated space (oblivious to the complex babble of enunciative practices taking place within it)
precedes and undergirds his description of the regulated space of the planned city, indi� erent to the
multiple trajectories unfolding in its spaces. The idealized constructions of theory mirror the panoptic
spaces of geometrical urban planning: “Within this ensemble,” de Certeau writes, “I shall try and locate
the practices that are foreign to the ‘geometrical’ or ‘geographic’ space of visual, panoptic or theoretical
constructions.” 14 And so, by analogy, just as the active citizen might manipulate and refi gure the space
of the city — which is given to her from without — so too creative intellectual subjects can put into play
the rigid codes of inherited ideological systems.
Two important senses of the word practice intersect here: practice designating the collective and
peripatetic improvisations of multiple inhabitants in the city connects to practice as the creative
exercise of an intellectual discipline by an individual. De Certeau’s cunning optimism suggests a
notion of practice capable of continually reworking the limits of a discipline from within. He o� ers
a way out of the either/or dilemma of practice seen exclusively as mechanical repetition (agent of
institutional authority), or the neo-avant-garde positions of transgression or critique. His view af-
fi rms that practices always unfold in time, moving on multiple and undisciplined trajectories. At
the same time it is a realistic vision, recognizing that it is impossible to e� ectively operate outside of
any discipline’s “fi eld of operations.” Just as the walker in the city produces “scandalous” fi gures out
of the geometric space of the city, there are tactical practices — nomad practices of writing, thinking
XX
or acting — that are capable of manipulating and reforming theory’s proscriptive spaces. When de
Certeau speaks, in this context of an “opaque and blind mobility” inserted into the “clear text of the
planned and readable city,” I would suggest that it could also be read as a way to practice theory, a
call for mobile and improper reworkings of the “clear text” of a given theoretical formulation. “Be on
the edge,” Deleuze and Guattari write, “take a walk like Virginia Woolf (never again will I say I am this,
I am that).” 15 The itinerant path of the walker in the city, or the nomad thinker in theory, is precisely
that which resists systematization, and makes room for the tactical improvisations of practice.
These essays have been constructed by following the trajectories of concepts unfolded in the course of
working.16 I wanted to trace the emergence of ideas in and through the materials and procedures of
the architectural work itself, and not as a legitimation from outside, in the form of written codes. Ar-
chitecture works by means of a necessarily mixed assemblage of procedures, and requires multiple
tactics of explanation. The purpose of writing is not so much to explain, or to justify a particular work
or working method, as it is a continual process of clarifi cation. In most cases, practical, experimental
work comes fi rst, and the writing down comes after. The activity of writing for me is part of the prac-
tice of architecture: something that happens alongside of drawing, building and teaching.
But the writing of an architect differs in significant ways from the writing of an historian or
a scholar. In part, it is marked by the technical and instrumental concerns of a working archi-
tect, a kind of “shoptalk:” comparing notes and testing techniques, finding out what works and
what doesn’t work, constantly on the lookout for new techniques. To define these essays as
part of an architectural practice is to recognize and accept the mixed character of architecture’s
procedures. To conceive this work as a practice is to work from examples, and not principles. It
necessitates a continual reference to specific instances of buildings, cities, drawings or texts. But
more significantly, it also means resisting the temptation to generalize the results in the form of a
project. Theory needs a project: a static construct, a persistent template of beliefs against which
individual actions are compared, and tested for conformance. In contrast, practices imply a shift to
performance, paying attention to consequences and effects. Not what a building, a text, or a draw-
ing means, but what it can do: how it operates in — and on — the world.
1998/2008
XXI
Stan Allen Aerial View, Extension of the Museo del Prado, 1998
XXII
Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientifi c Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970) 68.
William James, A Pluralistic Universe, eds. Frederick H. Burkhardt, Fredson Bowers, and Ignas K. Skrupskelis (Cambridge, MA and London:
Harvard University Press, 1977) 117.
There would appear to be two dominant positions today with regard to this question of architecture’s limits, and the regulating
power of the discipline. On the one hand, a conservative position that says that architecture’s fundamental questions of space, struc-