CHAPTER 3
The APA Ethics Code and
Ethical Decision Making
The APA’s Ethics Code provides a set of aspirational principles and
behavioral rules written broadly to apply to psychologists’ varied roles
and the diverse contexts in which the science and practice of psychology
are conducted. The five aspirational principles described in Chapter 2
represent the core values of the discipline of psychology that guide members in
recognizing in broad terms the moral rightness or wrongness of an act. As an
articulation of the universal moral values intrinsic to the discipline, the aspirational
principles are intended to inspire right action but do not specify what
those actions might be. The ethical standards that will be discussed in later
chapters of this book are concerned with specific behaviors that reflect the
application of these moral principles to the work of psychologists in specific
settings and with specific populations. In their everyday activities, psychologists
will find many instances in which familiarity with and adherence to specific
Ethical Standards provide adequate foundation for ethical actions. There
will also be many instances in which (a) the means by which to comply with a
standard are not readily apparent, (b) two seemingly competing standards
appear equally appropriate, (c) application of a single standard or set of standards
appears consistent with one aspirational principle but inconsistent with
another, or (d) a judgment is required to determine if exemption criteria for a
particular standard are met.
The Ethics Code is not a formula for solving these ethical challenges. The
Ethics Code provides psychologists with a set of aspirations and broad general
rules of conduct that must be interpreted and applied as a function of the unique
scientific and professional roles and relationships in which they are embedded.
Psychologists are not moral technocrats simply working their way through a
maze of ethical rules. Successful application of the principles and standards of the
Ethics Code involves a conception of psychologists as active moral agents committed
to the good and just practice and science of psychology. Ethical decision
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
30——PART I INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
making thus involves a commitment to applying the Ethics Code to construct
rather than simply discover solutions to ethical quandaries.
This chapter discusses the ethical attitudes and decision-making strategies that can
help psychologists prepare for, identify, and resolve ethical challenges as they continuously
emerge and evolve in the dynamic discipline of psychology. An opportunity to
apply these strategies is provided in the 10 case studies presented in Appendix B.
Ethical Commitment and Virtues
The development of a dynamic set of ethical standards for psychologists’
work-related conduct requires a personal commitment and lifelong effort to
act ethically; to encourage ethical behavior by students, supervisees, employees,
and colleagues; and to consult with others concerning ethical problems.
—APA (2010c, Preamble)
Ethical commitment refers to a strong desire to do what is right because it is right
(Josephson Institute of Ethics, 1999). In psychology, this commitment reflects a
moral disposition and emotional responsiveness that move psychologists to creatively
apply the APA’s Ethics Code principles and standards to the unique ethical
demands of the scientific or professional context.
The desire to do the right thing has often been associated with moral virtues or
moral character, defined as a disposition to act and feel in accordance with moral
principles, obligations, and ideals—a disposition that is neither principle bound
nor situation specific (Beauchamp & Childress, 2001; MacIntyre, 1984). Virtues are
dispositional habits acquired through social nurturance and professional education
that provide psychologists with the motivation and skills necessary to apply the
ideals and standards of the profession (see, e.g., Hauerwas, 1981; Jordan & Meara,
1990; May, 1984; National Academy of Sciences, 1995; Pellegrino, 1995). Fowers
(2012) describes virtues as the cognitive, emotional, dispositional, behavioral, and
wisdom aspects of character strength that motivates and enables us to act ethically
out of an attachment to what is good.
Focal Virtues for Psychology
Many moral dispositions have been proposed for the virtuous professional
(Beauchamp & Childress, 2001; Keenan, 1995; MacIntyre, 1984; May, 1984). For
disciplines such as psychology, in which codes of conduct dictate the general
parameters but not the context-specific nature of ethical conduct, conscientiousness,
discernment, and prudence are requisite virtues.
A conscientious psychologist is motivated to do what is right because it is right,
diligently tries to determine what is right, and makes reasonable attempts to
do the right thing.
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
Chapter 3 The APA Ethics Code and Ethical Decision Making——31
A discerning psychologist brings contextually and relationally sensitive
insight, good judgment, and appropriately detached understanding to determine
what is right.
A prudent psychologist applies practical wisdom to ethical challenges leading
to right solutions that can be realized given the nature of the problem and the
individuals involved.
Some moral dispositions can be understood as derivative of their corresponding
principles (Beauchamp & Childress, 2001). Drawing on the five APA General
Principles, Table 3.1 lists corresponding virtues.
The virtues considered most salient by members of a profession will vary
with differences in role responsibilities. Benevolence, care, and compassion are
often associated with the provision of mental health services. Prudence, discretion,
and trustworthiness have been considered salient in scientific decision
making. Scientists who willingly and consistently report procedures and findings
accurately are enacting the virtue of honesty (Fowers, 2012). Fidelity,
integrity, and wisdom are moral characteristics frequently associated with
teaching and consultation. Across all work activities the virtue of “self-care”
enables psychologists to maintain appropriate competencies under stressful
work conditions (see the Hot Topic “The Ethical Component of Self-Care” at
the end of this chapter.
“Openness to the other” has been identified as a core virtue for the practice of
multiculturalism (Fowers & Davidov, 2006). Openness is characterized by a personal
and professional commitment to applying a multicultural lens to our work
motivated by a genuine interest in understanding others rather than reacting to a
new wave of multicultural “shoulds” (Gallardo, Johnson, Parham, & Carter,
2009). It reflects a strong desire to understand how culture is relevant to the identification
and resolution of ethical challenges in research and practice, to explore
cultural differences, to respond to fluid definitions of group characteristics, to
recognize the realities of institutional racism and other forms of discrimination
on personal identity and life opportunities, and to creatively apply the profession’s
APA General Principles Corresponding Virtues
Principle A: Beneficence and
Nonmaleficence
Compassionate, humane, nonmalevolent, and
prudent
Principle B: Fidelity and Responsibility Faithful, dependable, and conscientious
Principle C: Integrity Honest, reliable, and genuine
Principle D: Justice Judicious and fair
Principle E: Respect for People’s Rights
and Dignity
Respectful and considerate
Table 3.1 APA Ethics Code General Principles and Corresponding Virtues
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
32——PART I INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
ethical principles and standards to each cultural context (Aronson, 2006; Fisher,
in press; Fowers & Davidov, 2006; Hamilton & Mahalik, 2009; Neumark, 2009;
Riggle, Rostosky, & Horne, 2010; D. W. Sue & Sue, 2003; Trimble, 2009; Trimble &
Fisher, 2006).
Can Virtues Be Taught?
No course could automatically close the gap between knowing what is
right and doing it.
—Pellegrino (1989, p. 492)
Some have argued that psychology professors cannot change graduate students’
moral character through classroom teaching, and therefore ethics education should
focus on understanding the Ethics Code rather than instilling moral dispositions to
right action. Without question, however, senior members of the discipline, through
teaching and through their own examples, can enhance the ability of students and
young professionals to understand the centrality of ethical commitment to ethical
practice. At the same time, the development of professional moral character is not to
simply know about virtue but to become good (P. A. Scott, 2003). Beyond the intellectual
virtues transmitted in the classroom and modeled through mentoring and
supervision, excellence of character can be acquired through habitual practice
(Begley, 2006). One such habit is that the virtuous graduate student and seasoned
psychologist are committed to lifelong learning and practice in the continued development
of moral excellence.
Ethical Awareness and Moral Principles
In the process of making decisions regarding their professional behavior,
psychologists must consider this Ethics Code, in addition to applicable
laws and psychology board regulations.
—APA (2010c, Introduction)
Lack of awareness or misunderstanding of an ethical standard is not itself
a defense to a charge of unethical conduct.
—APA (2010c, Introduction)
Ethical commitment is just the first step in effective ethical decision making. Good
intentions are insufficient if psychologists fail to identify the ethical situations to
which they should be applied. Psychologists found to have violated Ethical Standards
or licensure regulations have too often harmed others or damaged their own careers
or the careers of others because of ethical ignorance. Conscientious psychologists
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
Chapter 3 The APA Ethics Code and Ethical Decision Making——33
understand that identification of situations requiring ethical attention depends on
familiarity and understanding of the APA Ethics Code, relevant scientific and professional
guidelines, laws and regulations applicable to their specific work-related
activities, and an awareness of relational obligations embedded within each context.
Moral Principles and Ethical Awareness
To identify a situation as warranting ethical consideration, psychologists must
be aware of the moral values of the discipline. Although the Ethics Code’s General
Principles are not exhaustive, they do identify the major moral ideals of psychology
as a field. Familiarity with the General Principles, however, is not sufficient for good
ethical decision making. Psychologists also need the knowledge, motivation, and
coping skills to detect when situations call for consideration of these principles and
attempt to address these issues when and if possible before they arise (Crowley &
Gottlieb, 2012; Tjeltveit & Gottlieb, 2010; see also the Hot Topic “The Ethical
Component of Self Care” at the end of this chapter). Table 3.2 identifies types of
ethical awareness corresponding to each General Principle.
APA General
Principles Corresponding Ethical Awareness
Principle A:
Beneficence and
Nonmaleficence
Psychologists should be able to identify what is in the best interests of
those with whom they work, when a situation threatens the welfare of
individuals, and the competencies required to achieve the greatest
good and avoid or minimize harm.
Principle B: Fidelity
and Responsibility
Psychologists should be aware of their obligations to the individuals
and communities affected by their work, including their responsibilities
to the profession and obligations under the law.
Principle C: Integrity Psychologists should know what is possible before making professional
commitments and be able to identify when it is necessary to correct
misconceptions or mistrust.
Principle D: Justice Psychologists should be able to identify individual or group
vulnerabilities that can lead to exploitation and recognize when a
course of action would result in or has resulted in unfair or unjust
practices.
Principle E: Respect
for People’s Rights
and Dignity
Psychologists must be aware of special safeguards necessary to protect
the autonomy, privacy, and dignity of members from the diverse
populations with whom psychologists work.
Table 3.2 APA Ethics Code General Principles and the Ethical Awareness Necessary to Apply
the Principles
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
34——PART I INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
Ethical Awareness and Ethical Theories
Ethical theories provide a moral framework to reflect on conflicting obligations.
Unfortunately, ethical theories tend to emphasize one idea as the foundation for
moral decision making, and illustrative problems are often reduced to that one idea.
Given the complexity of moral reality, these frameworks are probably not mutually
exclusive in their claims to moral truth (Steinbock, Arras, & London, 2003).
However, awareness of the moral frameworks that might help address an ethical
concern can also help clarify the values and available ethical choices (Beauchamp &
Childress, 2001; Fisher, 1999; Kitchener, 1984).
Deception Research: A Case Example for the
Application of Different Ethical Theories
Since Stanley Milgram (1963) published his well-known obedience experiments,
the use of deception has become normative practice in some fields of psychological
research and a frequent source of ethical debate (Baumrind, 1964, 1985; Fisher &
Fyrberg, 1994). Deceptive techniques in research intentionally withhold information
or misinform participants about the purpose of the study, the methodology, or roles
of research confederates (Sieber, 1982). The methodological rationale for the use of
deception is that some psychological phenomena cannot be adequately understood if
research participants are aware of the purpose of the study. For example, deception has
been used to study the phenomenon of “bystander apathy effect,” the tendency for
people in the presence of others to observe but not help a person who is a victim of an
attack, medical emergency, or other dangerous condition (Latane & Darley, 1970). In
such experiments, false emergency situations are staged without the knowledge of the
research participants, whose reactions to the “emergency” are recorded and analyzed.
By its very nature, the use of deception in research creates what Fisher (2005a)
has termed the consent paradox. On the one hand intentionally deceiving participants
about the nature and purpose of a study conflicts with Principle C: Integrity
and with enforceable standards requiring psychologists to obtain fully informed
consent of research participants prior to study initiation. On the other hand by
approximating naturalistic contexts in which everyday behaviors take place, the use
of deception research can reflect Principle A: Beneficence and Nonmaleficence by
enhancing the ability of psychologists to generate scientifically and socially useful
knowledge that might not otherwise be obtained.
Below are examples of how different ethical theories might lead to different conclusions
about the moral acceptability of deception research. Readers should refer to
Chapter 11 for a more in-depth discussion of Standard 8.07, Deception in Research.
Deontology
Deontology has been described as “absolutist,” “universal,” and “impersonal”
(Kant, 1785/1959). It prioritizes absolute obligations over consequences. In this
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
Chapter 3 The APA Ethics Code and Ethical Decision Making——35
moral framework, ethical decision making is the rational act of applying universal
principles to all situations irrespective of specific relationships, contexts, or consequences.
This reflects Immanuel Kant’s conviction that ethical decisions cannot vary
or be influenced by special circumstances or relationships. Rather, a decision is
“moral” only if a rational person believes the act resulting from the decision should
be universally followed in all situations. For Kant, respect for the worth of all persons
was one such universal principle. A course of action that results in a person being
used simply as a means for others’ gains would be ethically unacceptable.
With respect to deception in research, from a deontological perspective, since we
would not believe it moral to intentionally deceive individuals in some other context,
neither potential benefits to society nor the effectiveness of participant
debriefing for a particular deception study can morally justify intentionally deceiving
persons about the purpose or nature of a research study. Further, deception in
research would not be ethically permissible since intentionally disguising the nature
of the study for the goals of research violates the moral obligation to respect each
participant’s intrinsic worth by undermining individuals’ right to make rational
and autonomous decisions regarding participation (Fisher & Fyrberg, 1994).
Utilitarianism
Utilitarian theory prioritizes the consequences (or utility) of an act over the
application of universal principles (Mill, 1861/1957). From this perspective, an ethical
decision is situation specific and must be governed by a risk–benefit calculus that
determines which act will produce the greatest possible balance of good over bad
consequences. An “act utilitarian” makes an ethical decision by evaluating the consequences
of an act for a given situation. A “rule utilitarian” makes an ethical decision
by evaluating whether following a general rule in all similar situations would
create the greater good. Like deontology, utilitarianism is impersonal: It does not
take into account interpersonal and relational features of ethical responsibility. From
this perspective, psychologists’ obligations to those with whom they work can be
superseded by an action that would produce a greater good for others (Fisher, 1999).
A psychologist adhering to act utilitarianism might decide that the potential
knowledge about social behavior generated by a specific deception study could
produce benefits for many members of society, thereby justifying the minimal risk
of harm and violation of autonomy rights for a few research participants. A rule
utilitarian might decide against the use of deception in all research studies because
the unknown benefits to society did not outweigh the potential harm to the discipline
of psychology if society began to see it as an untrustworthy science.
Communitarianism
Communitarian theory assumes that right actions derive from community
values, goals, traditions, and cooperative virtues. Accordingly, different populations
with whom a psychologist works may require different conceptualizations of
what is ethically appropriate (MacIntyre, 1989; Walzer, 1983). Unlike deontology,
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
36——PART I INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
communitarianism rejects the elevation of individual over group rights. Whereas
utilitarianism asks whether a policy will produce the greatest good for all individuals
in society, communitarianism asks whether a policy will promote the kind
of community we want to live in (Steinbock et al., 2003).
Scientists as members of a community of shared values have traditionally
assumed that (a) the pursuit of knowledge is a universal good and that (b) consideration
for the practical consequences of research will inhibit scientific progress
(Fisher, 1999; Sarason, 1984; Scarr, 1988). From this “community of scientists”
perspective, the results of deception research are intrinsically valuable, and standards
or regulations prohibiting deceptive research would deprive society of this
knowledge. Thus, communitarian theory may be implicitly reflected, at least in
part, in the acceptance of deception research in the APA Ethics Code (Standard 8.07,
Deception in Research) and in current federal regulations (Department of Health
and Human Services [DHHS], 2009) as representing the values of the scientific
community. At the same time little is known about the extent to which the “community
of research participants” shares the scientific community’s valuing of
deception methods (Fisher & Fyrberg, 1994).
Feminist Ethics
Feminist ethics, or an ethics of care, sees emotional commitment to act on behalf
of persons with whom one has a significant relationship as central to ethical decision
making. This moral theory rejects the primacy of universal and individual rights in
favor of relationally specific obligations (Baier, 1985; Brabeck, 2000; Fisher, 2000;
Gilligan, 1982). Feminist ethics also focuses our attention on power imbalances and
supports efforts to promote equality of power and opportunity. In evaluating the
ethics of deception research, feminist psychologists might view intentional deception
as a violation of interpersonal obligations of trust by investigators to participants
and as reinforcing power inequities by permitting psychologists to deprive
persons of information that might affect their decision to participate.
Ethical Absolutism, Ethical Relativism,
and Ethical Multiculturalism
The movement known as multiculturalism is reshaping moral dialogue in psychology
through its emphasis on inclusion, social justice, and mutual respect (Fowers &
Davidov, 2006).
Psychologists with high levels of ethical commitment and awareness are often
stymied by moral complexities that surface when psychological activities are conducted
in diverse contexts, cultures, or communities. For example, when applied to
ethical decision making across different contexts, the universal perspective of the
deontic position is indifferent to particular persons and situations. It therefore
rejects the influence of culture on the identification and resolution of ethical problems
in a manner that can lead to a one-size-fits-all form of ethical problem solving
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
Chapter 3 The APA Ethics Code and Ethical Decision Making——37
(Fisher, 1999). In sharp contrast, ethical relativism, often associated with some
forms of utilitarianism and communitarianism, denies the existence of universal or
common moral values characterizing the whole of human relationships, proposing
instead that the identification and resolution of ethical problems are unique to each
particular culture or community.
Ethical contextualism (Fisher, 1999, 2000, in press; Macklin, 1999) blends the two
approaches assuming that moral principles such as beneficence and respect for
autonomy are universally valued across diverse contexts and cultures, but the expression
of an ethical problem and the right actions to resolve it can be unique to the
cultural context. From this perspective, universal moral principles can mediate our
understanding of ethical meaning across diverse contexts without placing a priority
on the principles themselves over the moral frameworks of others (Walker, 1992).
Culture and Informed Consent: A Case Example
Take the example of the ethical challenge of obtaining informed consent for
mental health treatment for women suffering from posttraumatic stress disorder
(PTSD) in war-torn countries where cultural mores require that permission is
obtained from fathers, husbands, or brothers before a practitioner can offer services
to women.
A psychologist who is an ethical absolutist might refuse to obtain permission from
a male relative prior to obtaining consent from a female living in this culture on the
grounds that any action that privileges the opinion of a third party in a treatment or
research decision is a violation of a universal principle of respect for individual
autonomy. The cultural relativist, on the other hand, might interpret the cultural
mores dictating male privilege as evidence that respect for individual autonomy is not
a moral value in this particular culture; consequently, any action consistent with the
cultural norm (e.g., obtaining the male relative’s permission) is ethical.
The ethical contextualist would see the problem as one that requires consideration
of both a universal valuing of individual autonomy and its traditional expression
within this particular culture. A psychologist adopting this position would
seek to resolve the ethical problem in a manner consistent with both. For example,
examining the cultural meaning of this tradition, a psychologist might find that
women in this culture value the male gatekeeper role and see it as beneficial to
themselves and/or the stability of their families and communities. In this scenario,
principles of justice and respect for personhood might result in an ethical resolution
in which psychologists seek permission from a male relative before they obtain
informed consent from potential female clients/patients—at the same time making
it clear to both parties that the psychologist would respect the woman’s right to
refuse treatment irrespective of male permission.
Alternatively, the ethical contextualist might find that women living in this particular
cultural community view this tradition as repressive and fear harsh retaliation
if they disagree with the decision of their husbands or other male relatives. In
this scenario, drawing on the principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence
and respect for personhood, the psychologist might create a safe and confidential
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
38——PART I INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
opportunity for women to learn about and then consent or refuse the treatment on
their own without male involvement. For further discussion of these and related issues,
readers are referred to the Hot Topics in Chapter 5, on multicultural ethical competence,
and in Chapter 13, on the integration of religion and spirituality in therapy.
Ethical Competence and Ethical Decision Making
Too often, psychologists approach ethics as an afterthought to assessment or treatment
plans, research designs, course preparation, or groundwork for forensic or
consulting activities. Ethical planning based on familiarity with ethical standards,
professional guidelines, state and federal laws, and organizational and institutional
policies should be seen as integral rather than tangential to psychologists’ work.
Ethical Knowledge and Planning
Ethical Standards
Familiarity with the rules of conduct set forth in the Ethical Standards enables
psychologists to take preventive measures to avoid the harms, injustices, and violations
of individual rights that often lead to ethical complaints. For example, psychologists
familiar with the standards on confidentiality and disclosure discussed in
Chapter 7 will take steps in advance to (a) develop appropriate procedures to protect
the confidentiality of information obtained during their work-related activities;
(b) appropriately inform research participants, clients/patients, organizational
clients, and others in advance about the extent and limitations of confidentiality;
and (c) develop specific plans and lists of appropriate professionals, agencies, and
institutions to be used if disclosure of confidential information becomes necessary.
Guidelines
Good ethical planning also involves familiarity with guidelines for responsible
practice and science. The APA and other professional and scientific organizations
publish guidelines for responsible practice appropriate to particular psychological
activities. Guidelines, unlike ethical standards, are essentially aspirational and
unenforceable. As a result, compared with the enforceable Ethics Code standards,
guidelines can include recommendations for and examples of responsible conduct
with greater specificity to role, activity, and context. For example, Standard 2.01,
Boundaries of Competence, requires psychologists to limit their services to populations
and areas within their boundaries of competence, but as a general standard it
does not specify what such competencies are in different work contents. By contrast,
guidelines such as those for multicultural education, training, research, practice,
and organizational change for psychologists (APA, 2003) describe the specific
areas of training, education, or supervision that psychologists must have to perform
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
Chapter 3 The APA Ethics Code and Ethical Decision Making——39
their jobs competently. The Guidelines for Assessment of Dementia and Evaluation
of Age-Related Cognitive Change (APA, 2012a) provides a list of necessary competencies,
including memory changes associated with normative aging and the broad
range of medical, pharmacological, and mental health disorders (e.g., depression)
that can influence cognition in older adults. The crafters of guidelines developed by
APA constituencies usually attempt to ensure that their recommendations are consistent
with the most current APA Ethics Code—readers should be alert to instances
in which the 2010 Ethics Code renders some guideline recommendations adopted
prior to 2010 obsolete. Specific Guidelines are discussed throughout this book
where their relevance to ethical standards can be applied.
Laws, Regulations, and Policies
Another important element of information gathering is identifying and understanding
applicable laws, government regulations, and institutional and organizational
policies that may dictate or limit specific courses of action necessary to resolve
an ethical problem. There are state and federal laws and organizational policies
governing patient privacy, mandated reporting, research with humans and animals,
conduct among military enlistees and officers, employment discrimination, conflicts
of interest, billing, and treatment. Psychologists involved in forensically relevant
activities must also be familiar with rules of evidence governing expert testimony.
Readers may wish to refer to the Hot Topic in Chapter 12 on the implications of case
and federal law on the use of assessments in expert testimony.
As discussed in Chapter 2, only a handful of Ethical Standards require psychologists
to adhere to laws or institutional rules. However, choosing an ethical path that
violates law, institutional rules, or company policy can have serious consequences for
psychologists and others. Laws and policies should not dictate ethics, but familiarity
with legal and organizational rules is essential for informed ethical decision making.
When conflicts between ethics and law arise, psychologists consider the consequences
of the decision for stakeholders, use practical wisdom to anticipate and take
preventive actions for complications that can arise, and draw on professional virtues
to help identify the moral principles most salient for meeting professional role obligations
(Knapp, Gottlieb, Berman, & Handelsman, 2007).
Stakeholders
Ethical decision making requires sensitivity to and compassion for the views of
individuals affected by actions taken. Discussions with stakeholders can clarify the
multifaceted nature of an ethical problem, illuminate ethical principles that are in
jeopardy of being violated or ignored, and alert psychologists to potential unintended
consequences of specific action choices. By taking steps to understand the
concerns, values, and perceptions of clients/patients, research participants, family
members, organizational clients, students, IRBs or corporate compliance officers,
and others with whom they work, psychologists can avoid ethical decisions that
would be ineffective or harmful (Fisher, 1999, 2000).
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
40——PART I INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
Steps in Ethical Decision Making
Ethical commitment and well-informed ethical planning will reduce but not eliminate
ethical challenges that emerge during the course of psychologists’ work. Ethical
problems often arise when two or more principles or standards appear to be in
conflict, in unexpected events, or in response to unforeseen reactions of those with
whom a psychologist works. There is no ethical menu from which the right ethical
actions simply can be selected. Many ethical challenges are unique in time, place,
and persons involved. The very process of generating and evaluating alternative
courses of action helps place in vivid relief the moral principles underlying such
conflicts and stimulates creative strategies that may resolve or eliminate them.
Ethical decisions are neither singular nor static. They involve a series of steps,
each of which will be determined by the consequences of previous steps. Evaluation
of alternative ethical solutions should take a narrative approach that sequentially
considers the potential risks and benefits of each action. Understanding of relevant
laws and regulations as well as the nature of institutions, companies, or organizations
in which the activities will take place is similarly essential for adequate evaluation
of the reactions and restraints imposed by the specific ethical context.
A number of psychologists have proposed excellent ethical decision-making
models to guide the responsible conduct of psychological science and practice (e.g.,
Barnett & Johnson, 2008; Canter et al., 1994; Kitchener, 1984; Koocher & Keith-
Spiegel, 2008; Newman, Gray, & Fuqua, 1996; Rest, 1983; Staal & King, 2000).
Drawing on these models and the importance of ethical commitment, awareness,
and competence, an eight-step model is proposed:
Step 1: Develop and sustain a professional commitment to doing what is right.
Step 2: Acquire sufficient familiarity with the APA Ethics Code General Principles
and Ethical Standards to be able to anticipate situations that require ethical planning
and to identify unanticipated situations that require ethical decision making.
Step 3: Gather additional facts relevant to the specific ethical situation from
professional guidelines, state and federal laws, and organizational policies.
Step 4: Make efforts to understand the perspective of different stakeholders who
will be affected by the decision and consult with colleagues.
Step 5: Apply Steps 1 to 4 to generate ethical alternatives and evaluate each alternative
in terms of moral theories, General Principles and Ethical Standards,
relevant laws and policies, and consequences to stakeholders.
Step 6: Select and implement an ethical course of action.
Step 7: Monitor and evaluate the effectiveness of the course of action.
Step 8: Modify and continue to evaluate the ethical plan if feasible and necessary.
Appendix B contains 10 case studies that provide readers with the opportunity
to creatively apply to ethical challenges across a broad range of psychological work
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
Chapter 3 The APA Ethics Code and Ethical Decision Making——41
the ethical decision-making model described above and the knowledge they gain in
reading chapters throughout this book. The next section provides an example of
how the eight ethical decision-making steps can be applied to an ethical dilemma.
An Example of Ethical Decision Making
Dr. Ames conducts outpatient individual and group therapy for young adults with dual
diagnosis (substance dependence and anxiety disorders). Although Dr. Ames was careful
not to enter into the group those of her patients who were friends, partners, or relatives,
she has recently learned that two group members (James and Angela) have started to date
one another. In her next individual therapy session, Angela excitedly tells Dr. Ames that she
is pregnant and is planning to move in with James, the father of her baby. When asked if
she has seen a doctor, Angela replies that she does not have health insurance and has
nothing to worry about since neither she nor James have any diseases. Dr. Ames knows
from previous individual sessions with James that he is HIV positive. She asks Angela’s
permission to speak with James about their new situation and Angela agrees. During his
next session James tells Dr. Ames that he does not plan to tell Angela that he is HIV positive
because she would leave him. He also angrily reminds Dr. Ames that she is “sworn to
secrecy” because she promised that everything he told her, except child abuse or hurting
someone, would be confidential.
Step 1. Dr. Ames is committed to doing the right thing. She thinks of herself as honest,
judicious, respectful, and compassionate. She struggles with her desire to maintain
James’s confidentiality about his HIV status and her concern about the health
risks to Angela and her pregnancy (Standards 2.01, Maintaining Confidentiality;
3.05, Avoiding Harm).
Step 2. Dr. Ames reviews the Ethics Code standards. She realizes that because two of
her group therapy patients have unexpectedly entered into a romantic relationship
discussed only in their individual sessions that she is confronting an unforeseen
potentially harmful multiple relationship (Standard 3.05b, Multiple Relationships).
She realizes that her concerns regarding the health risks to Angela and her baby and
her conflict over maintaining James’s confidentiality can potentially compromise her
objectivity and effectiveness in performing her job. According to Standard 3.05b, she
must take reasonable steps to resolve the problem with due regard for the best interests
of all the affected persons.
Dr. Ames also recognizes that while it is important to protect James’s confidentiality
(Standard 4.01, Maintaining Confidentiality), the Ethics Code permits her to disclose
confidential information to protect others from harm (Standard 4.05, Disclosures). She
had thought that her informed consent procedure was consistent with ethical standards
since she did inform James and all her individual and group clients/patients of her legal
obligation to report child abuse and the possibility that disclosure could also occur to
protect others from harm (Standard 4.02, Discussing the Limits of Confidentiality).
However, although she was prepared to address issues of group members fraternizing
FOR THE USE OF UNIVERSITY OF PHOENIX STUDENTS AND FACULTY ONLY.
NOT FOR DISTRIBUTION, SALE, OR REPRINTING.
ANY AND ALL UNAUTHORIZED USE IS STRICTLY PROHIBITED.
Copyright © 2013 by SAGE Publications, Inc.
42——PART I INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND
outside of group, she had not anticipated that this type of situation would arise and she
was unsure about the answers to the following questions. Should James’s decision to
intentionally keep his HIV status secret and to continue to have unprotected sex with
Angela be considered “harm” to another person? Did the consent language adequately
inform Dr. Ames’s clients/patients that the risk of transmitting HIV would meet criteria
for disclosure? Are there prohibitions in state law against revealing a non-medical
client’s/patient’s HIV status? Is exposing a fetus to HIV infection included in the legal
definition of child abuse in Dr. Ames’s state?