Analysis Paper For A Finance Case, 5
THEORETICAL BASES FOR ANALYZING THE ETHICS OF A DECISION
Adapted from a chapter by John R. Deckop, in Vida Scarpello (ed). The Handbook of Human Resource Management Education: Promoting and Effective and Efficient Curriculum, Los Angeles: Sage Publications, 2008. Philosophers have pondered ethical questions for millennia, and have developed numerous
theoretical perspectives to aid in ethical decision-making. The range and depth of philosophical
theories on ethical decision-making can be daunting. So much so that arguably, presenting all
the major philosophical perspectives, and their nuances, is likely to fail from a pragmatic
standpoint because there is no way most students can absorb, much less apply on a day-to-day
level, so much material.
So this analysis will be restricted to the two “dominant” (Beauchamp & Bowie, 1997)
philosophical perspectives on ethics: utilitarianism and universalism, and will deal with only the
most general features of these theories. Things will be complicated a little, in that a third
theoretical perspective that is a subset of utilitarianism will also be discussed: profit
maximization.
The goal is to provide three perspectives (utilitarianism, profit maximization, and
universalism) on ethical decision-making that can actually be easily remembered, taught, and
used in daily decision-making. Later other perspectives will be overviewed, including theory
that challenges the two dominant perspectives.
Utilitarianism
The theory. Utilitarianism, developed primarily in the 19th century, can be understood by the
common phrases “The greatest good for the greatest number” and “The ends justify the means.”
The utilitarian believes that the potential outcomes of a decision should be analyzed to see who
benefits and who is harmed. The decision that results in the most total benefit compared to harm
is the best decision. The utilitarian is often portrayed figuratively as holding a scale, with the
benefits on one side being weighed against the harm on the other.
A critical aspect of this theory is that a decision can result in harm to some individuals and
still be the most ethical course of action. As long as benefit versus harm is maximized, the “ends
justify the means.” From a utilitarian perspective, an organizational downsizing for example
would be ethical as long as the good that comes from it, perhaps in the form of long-term
company health and shareholder value, outweighs the harm to dismissed and current employees,
and other stakeholders.
To conduct a utilitarian analysis, one must first conduct a stakeholder analysis. Put simply, a
stakeholder analysis assesses the effects of the alternate decisions facing the firm on all that are
affected by the decision. Specific methods for conducting stakeholder analyses can be complex,
though all make explicit the nature of the effects and why they will occur. Based on a
stakeholder analysis, a utilitarian can assess whether or not the overall benefit of a decision
exceeds the overall harm that the decision will cause.
Some criticisms of the theory. One criticism of utilitarianism is that the ends may not always
justify the means. Universalism, the other dominant ethical theory to be discussed below, argues
that humans have inherent worth and thus fundamental rights that should not be violated under
any circumstances. Thus, for example, while a utilitarian may defend drug testing, a universalist
might argue that drug testing fundamentally violates an employees right to privacy. Another
example relates to sweatshops – a utilitarian would argue that exceedingly poor treatment of
employees can be justified if the benefits to the firm and the community it resides in are large
enough. A universalist might disagree, arguing the exposing employees to extremely dangerous
conditions is not justified under any circumstances.
Another criticism of utilitarianism relates to potential self-serving biases of the person making
the decision. The utilitarian decision-maker in theory should weigh the benefits and harm too all
affected parties without bias. That may be difficult to do if the decision-maker has a significant
stake in the decision. Owners of sweatshops often reply that poor working conditions are
necessary to stay competitive and provide jobs for the community. Is this true, or just what the
owner tells himself as self-justification for getting rich? Similarly, a supervisor may fire a
subordinate with whom she has a conflict, telling herself that this termination is good for the
company, when in reality the decision may be self-serving. And even when the decision-maker
attempts to be unbiased with respect to self-interest, a variety of decision-making biases can
nevertheless result in unethical decisions when attempting a utilitarian solution (e.g., Messick &
Bazerman, 1996).
Profit Maximization
The theory. Profit maximization, as an ethical perspective, is a prescription of what has been
termed “neoclassical economics” (Hosmer, 2008). The basic principle of profit maximization is
that decisions made by firms, and employees within firms, should attempt to maximize firm
profit in the long-run, subject to assumptions or constraints.
The clearest explanation of profit maximization as an ethical imperative is probably the article
by Milton Friedman (1970), titled “The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase Its
Profits.” Profit maximization is actually a subset of utilitarianism, because Friedman and other
neoclassical economists argue that if all firms strive to maximize long-run profits (subject to
constraints) then the overall societal welfare, in terms of benefit versus harm, will be maximized
(Evan & Freeman, 1988). Why is this so? The explanation of this requires a detailed economic
analysis, which is usually covered in basic economics courses. As Hosmer (2008) suggests, it
may make sense to simply accept these economic arguments, as they are rigorously derived
given the assumptions that underly the model.
Profit maximization is a powerful tool for ethical decision making because the basic premise
– that business decisions should maximize long-run firm profit – is easy to understand. Yet its
prescriptions may seem “hard-hearted” to some people. For example, Friedman argued that
firms are unethical if they, for example, engage in pollution control beyond the requirements of
the law, if it hurts profits. Or if they hire the hard-core unemployed in order to contribute to the
social objective of reducing poverty. In both cases however, Friedman points out that the
decision-maker is spending someone else’s money (e.g., shareholders, customers) without their
consent. And in doing so, the firm would be making decisions that do not result in the most
economic benefit to society, according to this perspective.
Profit maximization can also be applied to more mundane, every day decisions. Should a
certain employee be terminated? The answer would be yes if, in the decision-maker’s judgment,
the termination is in the best interests of the firm. It would not matter if the employee was only
marginally a subpar performer, or if the termination would result in severe problems for the
employee and his family.
The part about the theory that has not been discussed thus far is the constraints. They are
critical, because the degree to which the constraints are met has direct implication as to whether
profit maximization can be considered an ethical decision basis. Each analysis based on profit
maximization must assess whether the decision maximizes long-run profit, and whether the
constraints are met. What are these constraints? Again, these are covered in a basic economic
course. Put simply, profit maximization and Friedman are saying that a business should
maximize profits while 1. obeying the law, 2., ensuring open and free competition, and 3. not
engaging in deception or fraud. Thus, if a firm makes a decision that in fact maximizes long-run
profit, but in doing so violates one or more of the constraints, profit maximization would say that
this decision is unethical. As discussed above this is because in violating a constraint the decision
does not contribute to the overall economic benefit of society.
The constraints of profit maximization sound straightforward, though the most common
criticism of this profit maximization as an ethical decision basis relates to the interpretation of
these constraints. This and other criticisms will be discussed next.
Criticisms of profit maximization. Profit maximization is considered a subset of utilitarianism
because, as mentioned, the theory states that if all firms seek to maximize profit, the overall
welfare of society will be maximized. But the constraints that must be met for the theory to
apply have undertones of other ethical perspectives. When Friedman says “without deception or
fraud,” he is sounding like a universalist, who would claim that some actions (e.g., deception) are
inherently wrong. He also states in his article that profit maximization should be subject to “the
basic rules of society, both those embodied in law, and those embodied in ethical custom.” How
does one define or identify ethical custom? Using a common philosophical metaphor, this puts
the theory on a “slippery slope,” because without a clear standard of “ethical” (which from a
tautological perspective puts us back at the beginning of all this discussion) almost any decision
could be supported or criticized using this theory. Those decision-making biases discussed
above with respect to utilitarianism in general also apply here. Self-serving and other biases may
well affect whether a decision-maker in a given instance determines that there is free
competition, or no fraud. Another main criticism of profit maximization is that as a utilitarian
theory, it could support doing significant harm to individuals in the name of profit (i.e., the ends
justify the means).
Universalism
The theory. Universalism is probably most associated historically with Immanuel Kant, who
wrote (primarily) in the 18th century. Two key principles are commonly associated with it:
“Never treat another inappropriately as a means to an ends,” and “Would you get what you want
if everyone did it, under similar circumstances?” This second principle, which Kant labeled the
“categorical imperative” bears resemblance to what in Christianity is called the golden rule, or
“Do unto others as you would have them do unto you.” Kant was trying, among other things, to
put “philosophical muscle” on the golden rule. Interestingly, the golden rule is not a principle
limited to Christianity; it is a fundamental tenet in every major religion in the world (Parliament
of the World's Religions, 1993).
Universalism is more than the golden rule, however, and is arguably more useful for
determining ethical decision in a business context. This is because the golden rule supposes the
decision maker is ethical to begin with (e.g., Trevino & Nelson, 2007). If not, the application of
the golden rule may not make much sense. For example, imagine that you are sitting in a café
looking out the window as you sip your drink. Across the street you witness a bank robbery, and
the man who just robbed the bank then walks into the café and sits next to you. He asks you to
tell the police when they arrive that he’s been sitting there for the past hour, thereby providing
him an alibi. Now, if you’re an ethical person (and don’t fear for your life!) you probably won’t
agree to lie. However, what if you’re a bank robber yourself, and think, “do unto others as you
would have them done unto you.” Well, following the golden rule, you’d want him to lie for
you, so that means that you’d lie for him. And that’s not ethical! As such, when applying
universalism, it is important to apply one or both of its key principles and not the golden rule.
Universalism directly challenges utilitarianism, in that the first statement above contradicts
the principle that the ends do not justify the means. It implies that employees have inherent
worth, and that a firm or manager that violates the employee’s inherent dignity and worth by
using them as a means to an end is acting unethically. For example, most would agree that sexual
harassment violates the victim’s fundamental rights as an employee, and is universally wrong, no
matter what.
When applying this perspective, you should ask yourself if no amount of good could make up
for the harm that you’re causing the individual. And if so, that means that the harm is
fundamentally wrong, and unethical according to universalism. This would be the case in the
sexual harassment example above. If not, however, then the action may well be ethical (or not
unethical) by universalist thinking. For example, let’s say an employer decides to downsize its
workforce by 20% in order to avoid bankruptcy. Terminating those employees certainly causes
them harm. However, many do not believe that an individual has a universal right to work for a
particular organization and never lose his/her job, under any circumstances. So a universalist
may consider this downsizing ethical.
The categorical imperative (second statement above) gets at notions of reversibility and
hypocrisy (Schumann, 2001). Consider an action by a manager – lying to an employee about her
chances of promotion in order to avoid her quitting the firm. The universalist would oppose this
because a world where all firms lied about such things would mean that employees, including
this one, would not believe anything about promotions in the first place, and as such, the intent of
the action (to retain the employee) would not be realized. In other words, if everyone did what
this manager did, he would not benefit from his action.
The categorical imperative can be considered a way to test whether you are correctly applying
the “don’t treat employees as a means” principle (Hosmer, 2008). The categorical imperative
implies that unless an action is morally right for others to do, then it is not morally right for you
to do. As such, all humans are of equal value. Treating people inappropriately as a means to an
ends denies the inherent worth of the individual, and denies them fundamental rights.
Criticisms of Universalism. A strict application of the categorical imperative is considered by
many to be difficult to apply in practice (Hosmer, 2008). For example, lying is prohibited. But
probably everyone lies at least occasionally, and few of us would consider all lies to be unethical.
Supervisors are often trained to provide supportive feedback to their subordinates, and it may be
effective in some circumstances to restrain brutal honesty when discussing performance with an
employee who has difficulty grasping something. Most of us would think that the dishonesty is
justified by the outcome – protecting the employee’s feelings of self-worth. This would be a
utilitarian way to look at the issue. Another criticism relates to the first formulation of
universalism. It’s hard to avoid treating others as a means to an end. We do it all the time –
arguably, professor and student treat the other as a means to an end. The key in applying the
perspective is the term “inappropriately.” A good guide would be to ask if the treatment violates
fundamental human rights of respect and dignity, such that no amount of good can make up for
it. But drawing this line can be difficult and introspection and consistency are necessary.
Universalism also suffers from the same potential of self-serving biases that the other ethical
theories face. The categorical imperative asks the decision-maker to situationalize the problem.
That is, under similar circumstances, would I be willing to make it a “universal law” for others to
do the same? A universalist decision-maker can be tempted to justify almost any action by
situationalizing the action in restrictive fashion. For example, a manager might be tempted to
skew a performance evaluation to give an employee a very good raise, which, let us say, would
benefit the manager politically in the organization. Without situationalizing the problem, the
action would not be justifiable because if all managers biased their performance evaluation
results when it was convenient to them, performance evaluation would not represent a rational
pay policy for the firm, which is one of its key objectives. So it would not be used, and this
manager could not benefit from her action. However, she could tell herself that she will do it
only this one time. Thus, she could rationalize that if there were a world where all managers
biased their performance evaluation results only once in their careers, then the intent of her
action would still be realized. The limited occurrence of the practice would still mean that
employees and firms would trust the validity of performance evaluation. This may be so, but
most of us would consider her action unethical.
APPLYING THE THEORIES IN EVERYDAY DECISION-MAKING
The purpose of ethical training is not to learn the concepts in order to get questions right on
an exam, or to impress others by dropping the names of impressive sounding theories. It is to
affect everyday decision-making. The three theories presented above – utilitarianism, profit
maximization, and universalism, are simple enough in their basic principles that they can be
easily remembered after you finish reading this.
Perhaps the next step after reading the theories is to think about which fits best with one’s
moral/religious upbringing and education. Which of these theories makes the most sense as a
basic rule of organizational life? If one had to pick one to characterize your concept of what is
right, which would it be? This theory can be the individual’s “home base” theory. It is the first
one to turn to when assessing the ethicality of a decision. It is applied to the situation, and if what
it says to do makes sense, the decision-maker acts accordingly.
However, its application may not make sense for a variety of reasons. Many people, in
understanding the criticisms of the various theories, are reluctant to commit to using one theory
in all circumstances. The theory may not provide a clear guide to action in a given case. Or
there might be a competing ethical principle that makes more sense in a given circumstance.
So it is also fine to be willing to apply other theories in situations where the home base theory
does not make sense. Philosophers, as proponents of one or another of these theories might
object, but until the philosophers or management theorists can identify one set of ethical
principles we can all agree upon, each of us has the responsibility to develop an ethical
framework for ourselves, one that we can live with and use.
Next, each theory will be discussed in terms of how it might be used as a home base theory,
and how it might be modified in given circumstances.
Let’s use utilitarianism is the home base theory. The decision-maker believes in weighing the
consequences of a decision against all affected stakeholders to the decision. It is acceptable if
decisions cause harm to some, as long as the benefit that others receives outweighs the harm.
However, in thinking through a particular decision, a question may be asked along the lines of
universalism: “Does my decision violate an employee’s fundamental rights as a human?” The
answer may be no to this. A termination or downsizing may be justified, assuming that
employees do not have a fundamental right to continued employment in a firm.
Alternatively, the may answer yes to this question. Perhaps a firm has decided to downsize a
group of employees. This may be an ethical decision on a utilitarian basis. However, let us say
top management proposes to not notify affected employees about the downsizing until the day of
termination. This action may also be acceptable from a utilitarian standpoint, if one believes that
the benefit to the firm from this practice will outweigh the harm to employees. However, one
may decide that this action, given the situation, is inherently wrong, because it violates
fundamental rights of affected employees. In this instance, it could be recommended that ample
notice be provided to employees of the downsizing, even while the decision-maker otherwise
makes decisions on a utilitarian basis.
Let us say profit maximization is the home base theory. One believes that the objective of
business decision-making should be to maximize the long-term profitability of the organization.
It can be an easy guide to apply, and it can be argued that it is an employee’s duty to make
decisions that benefit the firm, subject of course to the assumptions of the theory. But as with
utilitarianism, the question may arise: “Are there instances where the best interests of the firm
should take second place in my decision-making?” “Are their instances where the harm caused
to employees cannot be outweighed by any amount of profit?” This issue comes up, for
example, when the ethicality of sweatshops is considered. More and more, production has
shifted to countries in which labor standards afford workers and their communities little
protection from harmful practices, such as dangerous working conditions and environmental
pollution (e.g., Varley, 1998). Should a U.S. firm operate in another country using what would
clearly be considered inhumane treatment of workers by U.S. standards? Even if so, should a
firm provide only the absolute minimum in protection to workers and their communities dictated
by the law in that country (often almost none), in order to maximize profit? Many who believe
in profit maximization as a general principle would answer no to one or both of these questions.
One might instead argue that the firm should provide treat workers as humanely as possible,
while still allowing for a reasonable profit. This would be a utilitarian solution, one that does not
conform to strict profit maximization.
At a more mundane level, managers are faced everyday with issues of employee treatment.
Though the best interests of the firm may be one’s basic orientation, there may be situations
where a more utilitarian solution is appealing, such that the shareholders of the firm (the ultimate
beneficiaries of profit maximization) are considered but one stakeholder to the decision. And,
from a universalist perspective, there may be certain actions to employees that one would not be
willing to do under any circumstances, simply because the action is inherently wrong.
Let us say universalism is the home base theory. One may have been brought up that certain
things are fundamentally wrong, and certain actions never justifiable. Do not lie. Do not break
promises. Do not steal company property. Good treatment of employees is not necessarily a
means to benefit the company or other stakeholders in this view, but fundamentally the right
thing to do. Universalism is the home base theory, but as with the others, it may not be possible
or practical to apply it in all circumstances.
To exercise universalist principles, one must either the choose to work in a firm that has
similar values, or one must be willing to constantly challenge HRM policies or actions that are
considered wrong. It may be difficult to consistently practice universalistic principles in the
workplace. We all have different value systems, and honest assessments of a business policy
even by two universalists might contradict. For example, Grossman (2001), in applying
universalistic principles, suggests that incentive pay is a basic individual right. Conversely,
Heery (1999) argues that incentive pay, and the risk it imparts to employees, can represent a
fundamental injustice.
It may be difficult for an employee to find a firm to work for that has exactly the same
universal values. One cannot quit every time the firm does something, or asks one to do
something, that is inconsistent with one’s principles. Though one’s home base theory is
universalism, it may be necessary to search for a utilitarianism or profit maximization solution in
some circumstances.
Drawing Lines
As mentioned above, universalists cannot fight every fight, every time they see something in
their firm that they consider unethical. This same argument applies to other ethical theories. We
cannot try to change things, or quit, every time our ethical principles are violated. Thus, living
up to one’s ethical principles at work is also about learning where to draw the line – how bad
things must get to speak out, or quit.
And, most importantly, it is important to think about where these lines should be drawn ahead
of time - as in an educational environment versus the real world. Otherwise, the pressure of the
situation may result in drawing a line in a place looks reasonable at the time, but later is
perceived as unethical (e.g., McCoy, 1997). The single-minded pursuit of a goal, say getting a
project accomplished, can blind individuals to the ethical consequences of some of the decisions
made along the way. Sometimes decisions must be made within a very short time frame, maybe
even a split second. Maybe financial or family pressures make it extremely difficult to do what
ethical principles dictate. In all these situations, it is helpful to have thought through ethical
principles ahead of time. Each of the three ethical theories discussed above share one common
criticism: all can easily be misapplied if the decision-maker engages in self-deception. The
pressures of a situation may cause one to apply self-serving biases that while in the short-run
appear acceptable, in the long-run result in damage to one’s firm, career, or self in terms staying
true to ethical principles.
OTHER ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES
There are numerous other ethical perspectives that can be used as conceptual tools for ethical
decision-making. Some challenge the dominant perspectives discussed above, and other
complement these perspectives. Two categories will be discussed below: justice theories and the
theories related to the duty to care.
Justice
The goal of justice theories is to analyze whether a procedure, outcome, or both, is inherently
fair (Thorne, Ferrell, & Ferrell, 2003). Note that theories of procedural and distributive justice
are frequently discussed in textbooks, and are often based on philosophical concepts of justice.
However, the use of these theories in textbooks, as well as in academic research, is mainly as a
means to the ends of employee productivity (Greenwood, 2002). Justice, as a principle worthy
of realization in its own right in decision-making, has not received significant attention in texts.
Many justice theories relate to the distribution of wealth in society. For example, John
Rawls’ theory of distributive justice asks the decision-maker, when thinking about what is right,
to wear a “veil of ignorance” with respect to personal characteristics, such as race, family
background, special talents, etc. Then, one should make a decision that reflects this impartiality
to personal circumstances. Rawls argues that if we do this, our decisions would be to distribute
economic goods and services equally, unless an unequal distribution would work to everyone’s
advantage (Beauchamp & Bowie, 1997). The focus of this perspective is often on the
disadvantaged in society, and many of its implications imply the need for a more egalitarian
distribution of wealth both in society and within firms. However, Rawls does not argue for
complete equality. For example, differential compensation practices, such as incentive systems
for entrepreneurs, would be acceptable as long as the result was improved job opportunities for
the least advantaged members of society (Beauchamp & Bowie, 1997).
Another justice theory can be termed “contributive liberty” (Hosmer, 2008). In contrast to
theories of distributive justice, such as Rawls’ theory, this theory, developed by Robert Nozick,
focuses on an individual’s right to liberty in the process of decision-making. As such, it relates
to procedural, not distributive justice. From a resource allocation perspective, this theory
emphasizes the role of free markets, which, it argues, result in the fairest allocation of resources.
This theory represents a companion of sorts to profit maximization. While profit maximization
argues that market mechanisms produce the most societal welfare, contributive liberty argues for
the inherent justice of free markets.
All the theories up till this point focus on the individual – her rights, and the duties of the
decision-maker with respect to these rights. Another justice-based theory, communitarian
theory, focuses instead on the community. Rather than discuss the rights of the individual versus
the government or the firm, communitarian theory stresses the development of communal values,
and how those communal values should affect the individual (Beauchamp & Bowie, 1997). One
aspect of this theory is that too much focus on individual rights obscures the responsibility the
individual has to the collective. As a member of a community (the firm), an employee thus has
the responsibility to be, among other things, part of establishing a workplace that is fair and just
(Barrett, 1999).
The Duty to Care
Most well-known and established ethical theories, including all the theories discussed thus
far, focus on the development of an abstract set of ethical principles upon based on rights and
justice. There is no role for sensitivity to others, emotion, and relationships for their own sake in
these theories. Even universalism, with its focus on “doing unto others” emphasizes the
development of abstract principles not specifically related to particular individuals.
The duty to care is a label for several theories developed from a feminist tradition that
emphasize character traits that are valued in close personal relationships, such as sympathy and
compassion (Beauchamp & Bowie, 1997). One aspect of this work is to address societal
inequality of women, and how laws, and even ethical theories developed by men, have
contributed to this (Grimshaw, 1986).
Another focus is to advocate a basis for ethical decision-making based on care. One
prominent example is the work of Carol Gilligan (e.g., Gilligan, 1982). She asserts a framework
of care and compassion, traits often associated with women, as underlying moral reasoning and
ethical duty. Gilligen argues that a decision based on caring and concern for others can be as
ethical, or more ethical, than a decision based on adherence to a set of abstract principles.
This relates to duties in a variety of areas in the workplace (Beauchamp & Bowie, 1997).
Managers should exhibit sensitivity to employees’ personal problems not because it may result in
a more productive employee or protect against a lawsuit, but because it is the right thing to do.
We have the duty be sensitive to the points of view of others. When there are conflicting rights,
this sensitivity can help in finding solutions where all party’s voices and perspectives are heard.
Feminist thinking and the duty to care also involve metaphors in the workplace. Metaphors more
commonly associated with men, such as sports and war, often reflect competition and conflict.
Metaphors more commonly associated with women, such as relationships and family, are often
seen as “soft” and not as important, despite the fact that these orientations may be correct
(Beauchamp & Bowie, 1997).
REFERENCES
Aspen Institute (2002). Where will they lead? Aspen, CO: Institute for Social Innovation
Through Business.
Barrett, E. (1999). Justice in the workplace? Normative ethics and the critique of human
resource management. Personnel Review, 28 (4), 307-318.
Beauchamp, T. L. & Bowie, N. E. (1997). Ethical Theory and Business. Upper Saddle River,
NJ: Prentice Hall. 5th Edition.
Cassidy, J. (2002). The greed cycle. New Yorker, 78, September 23, 64-77.
Deckop, J.R. (2006). Human Resource Management Ethics. Greenwich, CT: Information Age
Publishing.
Eichenwald, K. (2002). Even if heads roll, mistrust will live on. The New York Times, Oct. 6.
Evan, W. M., & Freeman, R. E. (1988). A Stakeholder Theory of the Modern Corporation:
Kantian Capitalism. In T. L. Beauchamp and N. Bowie (eds.), Ethical Theory and
Business. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Friedman, M. (1970). The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York
Times Magazine, September 13.
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development.
Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Gladwell, M. (2002). The talent myth: Are smart people overrated? New Yorker, 78, July 22, 28-
33.
Gomez-Mejia, L. R., Balkin, D. B., & Cardy, R. L. (2007). Managing Human Resources. Upper
Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall. 5th edition.
Gravett, L. (2003). HRM Ethics: Perspectives for a New Millennium. Cincinnati: Atomic Dog
Publishing.
Greenwood, M. R. (2002). Ethics and HRM: A review and conceptual analysis. Journal of
Business Ethics, 36 (3), 261-278.
Grimshaw, J. (1986). Philosophy and Feminist Thinking. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Grossman, W. (2001). Resolving human resource dilemmas through international human
resource management: A transaction cost economics perspective. Human Resource
Management Review, 11, 55-72.
Heery, E. (1999). Risk, representation, and the new pay. Personnel Review, 25, (6), 54-65.
Hosmer, L. T. (2008). The Ethics of Management. Boston: McGraw-Hill. 6th Edition.
McCoy, B. H. (1997). The parable of the sadhu. Harvard Business Review, 75 (3), 54-61,
McShulskis, E. (1997). Job stress can prompt unethical behavior. HR Magazine, 42 (7), 22-23.
Messick, D. M. & Bazerman, M. H. (1996). Ethical leadership and the psychology of decision
making. Sloan Management Review, 37 (2) 9-22.
O'Leary-Kelly, A. M. (2001). Sexual harassment as unethical behavior: The role of moral
intensity. Human Resource Management Review, 11, 73-92.
Payne, S. L. & Wayland, R. F. (1999). Ethical obligation and diverse values assumptions in
HRM. International Journal of Manpower, 20, 5/6, 297-308.
Parliament of the World's Religions. (1993). Towards A global ethic. Chicago, IL: Council for a
Parliament of the World's Religions.
Schumann, P. L. (2001). A moral principles framework for human resource management ethical
analysis. Human Resource Management Review, 11, 93-111.
Thorne McAlister, D. T., Ferrell, O. C., & Ferrell, L. (2005). Business and Society. Boston:
Houghton Mifflin Company. 2nd Edition.
Townley, B. (1994). Reframing Human Resource Management: Power, Ethics, and the Subject
at Work. London: Sage Publications.
Varley, P. (1998). The Sweatshop Quandary: Corporate Responsibility on the Global Frontier.
New York: Investor Responsibility Research Center.
Winstanley, D. & Woodall, J. (2000). Ethical Issues in Contemporary Human Resource
Management. New York: St. Martin’s Press.